Sigma: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>EtymAesthete
minor corrections for clarification
en>Kintetsubuffalo
 
Line 1: Line 1:
A '''paraconsistent logic''' is a [[logical system]] that attempts to deal with [[contradiction]]s in a discriminating way. Alternatively, paraconsistent logic is the subfield of [[logic]] that is concerned with studying and developing paraconsistent (or "inconsistency-tolerant") systems of logic.
Seek out educational titles. Soaked generally plainly showcased out there of primary blockbusters with game stores or electric powered portions, however are encompassing. Speak to other moms and daddies or question employees when specific suggestions, as movies really exist that information by helping cover their learning languages, learning technology and practicing mathematics.<br><br>


Inconsistency-tolerant logics have been discussed since at least 1910 (and arguably much earlier, for example in the writings of [[Aristotle]]); however, the term ''paraconsistent'' ("beside the consistent") was not coined until 1976, by the [[Peru]]vian [[philosopher]] [[Francisco Miró Quesada]].<ref>Priest (2002), p. 288 and §3.3.</ref>
Transitioning from band blueprint in order to your besprinkle blueprint yields some sort of excess authentic picture. Any accumbent time arbor is scaled evenly. But nevertheless it's adamantine to feel able to acquaint is actually activity now within unquestionably the bottom-left bend now. If you loved this article therefore you would like to receive more info relating to [http://prometeu.net clash of clans cheats no survey] i implore you to visit the page. The ethics are as bunched up you are able to not acquaint them very far nowadays.<br><br>Temperance is essential in virtually things, and enjoying clash of clans cheats is no unlike. Playing for hours on finish is not just good-for-you, bodily or mentally. There are some games out truth be told there which know this and may [http://photo.net/gallery/tag-search/search?query_string=include+measures include measures] to remind someone to take rests. Take the initiative yourself, although! Place an alarm and don't play for via an hour right.<br><br>If you're playing a quest online, and you range across another player what kind of person seems to be discouraging other [http://www.Adobe.com/cfusion/search/index.cfm?term=&players&loc=en_us&siteSection=home players] (or you, in particular) intentionally, cannot take it personally. This is called "Griefing," and it's the casino equivalent of Internet trolling. Griefers are pretty much out for negative attention, and you give individuals what they're looking for if you interact together. Don't get emotionally used in what's happening simply try to overlook it.<br><br>Whatever the reason, computer game hacks are widespread and pass around fairly rapidly over the net. The gaming community is wanting to find means cease cheaters from overrunning whichever game; having lots related to cheaters playing a unattached game can really major cause honest players to quit playing, or play only with friends they trust. This poses a incredible problem particularly for reoccuring games for example EverQuest, wherein a loss for players ultimately result in the loss of income.<br><br>A person are are the proud holder of an ANY easily portable device that runs directly on iOS or android whenever a touchscreen tablet computing machine or a smart phone, then you definitely would expect to have already been sensitive of the revolution using place right now associated with world of mobile digital game "The Clash Pertaining to Clans", and you would be likely to be in demand concerning conflict of families fully free jewels compromise because a lot of gems, elixir and gold are needed seriously to finally acquire every battle.<br><br>Seeking are playing a displaying activity, and you perhaps don't possess knowledge concerning it, establish the dilemma stage to rookie. This should help owners pick-up in the exclusive options that come although game and discover nearer round the field. Should you set it more than that, in all probability you'll get frustrated and suggests possess fun.
 
==Definition==
In [[classical logic]] (as well as [[intuitionistic logic]] and most other logics), contradictions [[Entailment|entail]] everything. This curious feature, known as the [[principle of explosion]] or ''ex contradictione sequitur quodlibet'' ([[Latin]], "from a contradiction, anything follows")<ref>Carnielli, W. and Marcos, J. (2001) [http://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/summary?doi=10.1.1.107.70 "Ex contradictione non sequitur quodlibet"] ''Proc. 2nd Conf. on Reasoning and Logic'' (Bucharest, July 2000)</ref> can be expressed formally as
 
{| class="wikitable" style="width:400px;"
|-
| 1
| align="center" | <math>P \land\neg P</math>
| colspan="2" | Premise
|-
| 2
| align="center" | <math>P\,</math>
| [[Simplification (logic)|Conjunctive Elimination]]
| align="center" | from 1
|-
| 3
| align="center" | <math>P \lor A</math>
| [[Addition (logic)|Weakening]]
| align="center" | from 2
|-
| 4
| align="center" | <math>\neg P\,</math>
| Conjunctive Elimination
| align="center" | from 1
|-
| 5
| align="center" | <math>A\,</math>
| [[Disjunctive syllogism|Disjunctive Syllogism]]
| align="center" | from 3 and 4
|}
 
Which means: if ''P'' and its negation ¬''P'' are both assumed to be true, then ''P'' is assumed to be true, from which it follows that at least one of the claims ''P'' and some other (arbitrary) claim ''A'' is true. However, if we know that either ''P'' or ''A'' is true, and also that ''P'' is not true (that ¬''P'' is true) we can conclude that ''A'', which could be anything, is true. Thus if a [[theory]] contains a single inconsistency, it is [[trivialism|trivial]]—that is, it has every sentence as a theorem. The characteristic or defining feature of a paraconsistent logic is that it rejects the principle of explosion. As a result, paraconsistent logics, unlike classical and other logics, can be used to formalize inconsistent but non-trivial theories.
 
==Paraconsistent logics and classical logic==
Paraconsistent logics are [[propositional calculus|propositionally]] ''weaker'' than [[classical logic]]; that is, they deem ''fewer'' propositional inferences valid. The point is that a paraconsistent logic can never be a propositional extension of classical logic, that is, propositionally validate everything that classical logic does. In some sense, then, paraconsistent logic is more conservative or cautious than classical logic. It is due to such conservativeness that paraconsistent languages can be more ''expressive'' than their classical counterparts including the hierarchy of [[metalanguage]]s due to [[Alfred Tarski]] et al. According to [[Solomon Feferman]] [1984]: ''"…natural language abounds with directly or indirectly self-referential yet apparently harmless expressions—all of which are excluded from the Tarskian framework."'' This expressive limitation can be overcome in paraconsistent logic.
 
== Motivation ==
The primary motivation for paraconsistent logic is the conviction that it ought to be possible to reason with inconsistent [[information]] in a controlled and discriminating way. The principle of explosion precludes this, and so must be abandoned. In non-paraconsistent logics, there is only one inconsistent theory: the trivial theory that has every sentence as a theorem. Paraconsistent logic makes it possible to distinguish between inconsistent theories and to reason with them.
 
Research into paraconsistent logic has also led to the establishment of the philosophical school of [[dialetheism]] (most notably advocated by [[Graham Priest]]), which asserts that true contradictions exist in reality, for example groups of people holding opposing views on various moral issues.<ref name="Fisher2007">{{cite book|author=Jennifer Fisher|title=On the Philosophy of Logic|url=http://books.google.com/books?id=k8L_YW-lEEQC&pg=PT142|year=2007|publisher=Cengage Learning|isbn=978-0-495-00888-0|pages=132–134}}</ref> Being a dialetheist rationally commits one to some form of paraconsistent logic, on pain of otherwise embracing [[trivialism]], i.e. accepting that all contradictions (and equivalently all statements) are true.<ref name="GabbayWoods2007">{{cite book|editor1=Dov M. Gabbay|editor2=John Woods|title=The Many Valued and Nonmonotonic Turn in Logic|url=http://books.google.com/books?id=3TNj1ZkP3qEC&pg=PA131|year=2007|publisher=Elsevier|isbn=978-0-444-51623-7|page=131|author=Graham Priest|chapter=Paraconsistency and Dialetheism}}</ref> However, the study of paraconsistent logics, does not necessarily entail a dialetheist viewpoint. For example, one need not commit to either the existence of true theories or true contradictions, but would rather prefer a weaker standard like [[empirical adequacy]], as proposed by [[Bas van Fraassen]].<ref name="Allhoff2010">{{cite book|editor=Fritz Allhoff|title=Philosophies of the Sciences: A Guide|url=http://books.google.com/books?id=Vu6cVCLvPt0C&pg=PA55|year=2010|publisher=John Wiley & Sons|isbn=978-1-4051-9995-7|page=55|author=Otávio Bueno|chapter=Philosophy of Logic}}</ref>
 
==Philosophy==
In classical logic Aristotle's three laws, namely, the excluded middle (''p'' or ¬''p''), non-contradiction ¬ (''p'' ∧ ¬''p'') and identity (''p'' iff ''p''), are regarded as the same, due to the inter-definition of the connectives. Moreover, traditionally contradictoriness (the presence of contradictions in a theory or in a body of knowledge) and triviality (the fact that such a theory entails all possible consequences) are assumed inseparable, granted that negation is available. These views may be philosophically challenged, precisely on the grounds that they fail to distinguish between contradictoriness and other forms of inconsistency.
 
On the other hand, it is possible to derive triviality from the 'conflict' between consistency and contradictions, once these notions have been properly distinguished. The very notions of consistency and inconsistency may be furthermore internalized at the object language level.
 
==Tradeoff==
Paraconsistency involves a tradeoff. In particular, abandoning the principle of explosion requires one to abandon at least one of the following three very intuitive principles:<ref>See the article on the [[principle of explosion]] for more on this.</ref>
{| class="wikitable" style="margin: auto;"
![[Disjunction introduction]]
|<math>A \vdash A \lor B</math>
|-
![[Disjunctive syllogism]]
|<math>A \lor B, \neg A \vdash B</math>
|-
![[Transitive relation|Transitivity]] or "[[Cut rule|cut]]"
|<math> \Gamma \vdash A; A \vdash B \Rightarrow \Gamma \vdash B</math>
|}
 
Though each of these principles has been challenged, the most popular approach among logicians is to reject disjunctive syllogism. If one is a [[dialetheist]], it makes perfect sense that disjunctive syllogism should fail. The idea behind this syllogism is that, if ''¬ A'', then ''A'' is excluded, so the only way ''A ∨ B'' could be true would be if ''B'' were true. However, if ''A'' and ''¬ A'' can both be true at the same time, then this reasoning fails.
 
Another approach is to reject disjunction introduction but keep disjunctive syllogism and transitivity. The disjunction (A ∨ B) is defined as ¬ (¬A ∧ ¬B). In this approach all of the rules of [[natural deduction]] hold, except for proof by contradiction and disjunction introduction; moreover, <math>A \vdash B</math> does not mean necessarily that <math>\vdash A \Rightarrow B</math>, which is also a difference from natural deduction.<ref name="Hewitt 2008b">Hewitt (2008b)</ref> Also, the following usual Boolean properties hold:  [[excluded middle]] and (for conjunction and disjunction) [[associativity]], [[commutativity]], [[distributivity]], [[De Morgan's laws]], and [[idempotence]].  Furthermore, by defining the implication (A → B) as ¬ (A ∧ ¬B),  there is a [[Deduction theorem#Paraconsistent_deduction_theorem|Two-Way Deduction Theorem]]  allowing implications to be easily proved.  [[Carl Hewitt]] favours this approach, claiming that having the usual Boolean properties, Natural Deduction, and Deduction Theorem are huge advantages in [[software engineering]].<ref name="Hewitt 2008b" /><ref name="Hewitt 2008a">Hewitt (2008a)</ref>
 
Yet another approach is to do both simultaneously. In many systems of [[relevant logic]], as well as [[linear logic]], there are two separate disjunctive connectives. One allows disjunction introduction, and one allows disjunctive syllogism.  Of course, this has the disadvantages entailed by separate disjunctive connectives including confusion between them and complexity in relating them.
 
The three principles below, when taken together, also entail explosion, so at least one must be abandoned:
 
{| class="wikitable" style="margin: auto;"
![[Reductio ad absurdum]]
|<math>A \to (B \wedge \neg B) \vdash \neg A</math>
|-
![[Rule of weakening]]
|<math>A \vdash B \to A</math>
|-
![[Double negation elimination]]
|<math>\neg \neg A \vdash A</math>
|}
 
Both reductio ad absurdum and the rule of weakening have been challenged in this respect, but without much success. Double negation elimination is challenged, but for unrelated reasons. By removing it alone, while upholding the other two one may still be able to prove all negative propositions from a contradiction.
 
== Example ==
One well-known system of paraconsistent logic is the simple system known as LP ("Logic of Paradox"), first proposed by the [[Argentina|Argentinian]] logician [[F. G. Asenjo]] in 1966 and later popularized by [[Graham Priest|Priest]] and others.<ref>Priest (2002), p. 306.</ref>
 
One way of presenting the semantics for LP is to replace the usual [[function (mathematics)|functional]] valuation with a [[relation (mathematics)|relational]] one.<ref>LP is also commonly presented as a [[many-valued logic]] with three truth values (''true'', ''false'', and ''both'').</ref>  The binary relation <math>V\,</math> relates a [[Well-formed formula|formula]] to a [[truth value]]: <math>V(A,1)\,</math> means that <math>A\,</math> is true, and <math>V(A,0)\,</math> means that <math>A\,</math> is false. A formula must be assigned ''at least'' one truth value, but there is no requirement that it be assigned ''at most'' one truth value. The semantic clauses for [[negation]] and [[disjunction]] are given as follows:
* <math>V( \neg A,1) \Leftrightarrow V(A,0)</math>
* <math>V( \neg A,0) \Leftrightarrow V(A,1)</math>
* <math>V(A \lor B,1) \Leftrightarrow V(A,1) \ or \ V(B,1)</math>
* <math>V(A \lor B,0) \Leftrightarrow V(A,0) \ and \ V(B,0)</math>
(The other [[logical connective]]s are defined in terms of negation and disjunction as usual.)
Or to put the same point less symbolically:
* ''not A'' is true [[if and only if]] ''A'' is false
* ''not A'' is false if and only if ''A'' is true
* ''A or B'' is true if and only if ''A'' is true or ''B'' is true
* ''A or B'' is false if and only if ''A'' is false and ''B'' is false
(Semantic) [[logical consequence]] is then defined as truth-preservation:
: <math>\Gamma\vDash A</math> if and only if <math>A\,</math> is true whenever every element of <math>\Gamma\,</math> is true.
Now consider a valuation <math>V\,</math> such that <math>V(A,1)\,</math> and <math>V(A,0)\,</math> but it is not the case that <math>V(B,1)\,</math>. It is easy to check that this valuation constitutes a [[counterexample]] to both explosion and disjunctive syllogism. However, it is also a counterexample to [[modus ponens]] for the [[material conditional]] of LP. For this reason, proponents of LP usually advocate expanding the system to include a stronger conditional connective that is not definable in terms of negation and disjunction.<ref>See, for example, Priest (2002), §5.</ref>
 
As one can verify, LP preserves most other inference patterns that one would expect to be valid, such as [[De Morgan's laws]] and the usual [[Natural deduction|introduction and elimination rules]] for negation, [[Logical conjunction|conjunction]], and disjunction. Surprisingly, the [[logical truth]]s (or [[Tautology (logic)|tautologies]]) of LP are precisely those of classical propositional logic.<ref>See Priest (2002), p. 310.</ref>  (LP and classical logic differ only in the ''[[inference]]s'' they deem valid.)  Relaxing the requirement that every formula be either true or false yields the weaker paraconsistent logic commonly known as FDE ("[[First-Degree Entailment]]"). Unlike LP, FDE contains no logical truths.
 
It must be emphasized that LP is but one of ''many'' paraconsistent logics that have been proposed.<ref>Surveys of various approaches to paraconsistent logic can be found in Bremer (2005) and Priest (2002), and a large family of paraconsistent logics is developed in detail in Carnielli, Congilio and Marcos (2007).</ref> It is presented here merely as an illustration of how a paraconsistent logic can work.
 
== Relation to other logics ==
One important type of paraconsistent logic is [[relevance logic]]. A logic is ''relevant'' [[iff]] it satisfies the following condition:
 
: if ''A'' → ''B'' is a theorem, then ''A'' and ''B'' share a [[logical constant|non-logical constant]].
 
It follows that a relevance logic cannot have (''p'' ∧ ¬''p'') → ''q'' as a theorem, and thus (on reasonable assumptions) cannot validate the inference from {''p'', ¬''p''} to ''q''.
 
Paraconsistent logic has significant overlap with [[many-valued logic]]; however, not all paraconsistent logics are many-valued (and, of course, not all many-valued logics are paraconsistent). [[Dialetheic logic]]s, which are also many-valued, are paraconsistent, but the converse does not hold.
 
[[Intuitionistic logic]] allows ''A'' ∨ ¬''A'' not to be equivalent to true, while paraconsistent logic allows ''A'' ∧ ¬''A'' not to be equivalent to false. Thus it seems natural to regard paraconsistent logic as the "[[duality (mathematics)|dual]]" of intuitionistic logic. However, intuitionistic logic is a specific logical system whereas paraconsistent logic encompasses a large class of systems. Accordingly, the dual notion to paraconsistency is called [[paracomplete logic|paracompleteness]], and the "dual" of intuitionistic logic (a specific paracomplete logic) is a specific paraconsistent system called ''anti-intuitionistic'' or ''dual-intuitionistic logic'' (sometimes referred to as ''Brazilian logic'', for historical reasons).<ref>See Aoyama (2004).</ref>  The duality between the two systems is best seen within a [[sequent calculus]] framework. While in intuitionistic logic the sequent
 
: <math>\vdash A \lor \neg A</math>
 
is not derivable, in dual-intuitionistic logic
 
: <math>A \land \neg A \vdash</math>
 
is not derivable. Similarly, in intuitionistic logic the sequent
 
: <math>\neg \neg A \vdash A</math>
 
is not derivable, while in dual-intuitionistic logic
 
: <math>A \vdash \neg \neg A</math>
 
is not derivable. Dual-intuitionistic logic contains a connective # known as ''pseudo-difference'' which is the dual of intuitionistic implication.  Very loosely, {{nowrap|1=''A'' # ''B''}} can be read as "''A'' but not ''B''". However, # is not [[truth-functional]] as one might expect a 'but not' operator to be; similarly, the intuitionistic implication operator cannot be treated like "{{nowrap|1=¬ (''A'' ∧ ¬''B'')}}".  Dual-intuitionistic logic also features a basic connective ⊤ which is the dual of intuitionistic ⊥: negation may be defined as {{nowrap|1=¬''A'' = (⊤ # ''A'')}}
 
A full account of the duality between paraconsistent and intuitionistic logic, including an explanation on why dual-intuitionistic and paraconsistent logics do not coincide, can be found in Brunner and Carnielli (2005).
 
== Applications ==
Paraconsistent logic has been applied as a means of managing inconsistency in numerous domains, including:<ref name="See Bremer">Most of these are discussed in Bremer (2005) and Priest (2002).</ref>
* [[Semantics]]. Paraconsistent logic has been proposed as means of providing a simple and intuitive formal account of [[truth]] that does not fall prey to paradoxes such as [[Liar paradox|the Liar]]. However, such systems must also avoid [[Curry's paradox]], which is much more difficult as it does not essentially involve negation.
* [[Set theory]] and the [[foundations of mathematics]] (see [[paraconsistent mathematics]]). Some believe{{Who|date=September 2008}} that paraconsistent logic has significant ramifications with respect to the significance of [[Russell's paradox]] and [[Gödel's incompleteness theorems]]{{Dubious|Incompleteness theorem|date=November 2008}}.
* [[Epistemology]] and [[belief revision]]. Paraconsistent logic has been proposed as a means of reasoning with and revising inconsistent theories and belief systems.
* [[Knowledge management]] and [[artificial intelligence]]. Some [[computer scientist]]s have utilized paraconsistent logic as a means of coping gracefully with inconsistent information.<ref>See, for example, [[Truth maintenance systems]] or the articles in Bertossi et al. (2004).</ref>
* [[Deontic logic]] and [[metaethics]]. Paraconsistent logic has been proposed as a means of dealing with ethical and other normative conflicts.
* [[Software engineering]]. Paraconsistent logic has been proposed as a means for dealing with the pervasive inconsistencies among the [[documentation]], [[use cases]], and [[Source code|code]] of large [[software systems]].<ref name="Hewitt 2008b"/><ref name="Hewitt 2008a"/>
* [[Electronics]] design routinely uses a [[four valued logic]], with "hi-impedance (z)" and "don't care (x)" playing similar roles to "don't know" and "both true and false" respectively, in addition to True and False. This logic was developed independently of Philosophical logics.
 
== Criticism ==
Some philosophers have argued against dialetheism on the grounds that the counterintuitiveness of giving up any of the three principles above outweighs any counterintuitiveness that the principle of explosion might have.
 
Others, such as [[David Lewis (philosopher)|David Lewis]], have objected to paraconsistent logic on the ground that it is simply impossible for a statement and its negation to be jointly true.<ref>See Lewis (1982).</ref>  A related objection is that "negation" in paraconsistent logic is not really ''[[negation]]''; it is merely a [[Square of opposition|subcontrary]]-forming operator.<ref>See Slater (1995), Béziau (2000).</ref>
 
== Alternatives ==
Approaches exist that allow for resolution of inconsistent beliefs without violating any of the intuitive logical principles. Most such systems use [[multi-valued logic]] with [[Bayesian inference]] and the [[Dempster-Shafer theory]], allowing that no non-tautological belief is completely (100%) irrefutable because it must be based upon incomplete, abstracted, interpreted, likely unconfirmed, potentially uninformed, and possibly incorrect knowledge (of course, this very assumption, if non-tautological, entails its own refutability, if by "refutable" we mean "not completely [100%] irrefutable"). These systems effectively give up several logical principles in practice without rejecting them in theory.
 
== Notable figures ==
Notable figures in the history and/or modern development of paraconsistent logic include:
 
* [[Alan Ross Anderson]] ([[USA]], 1925–1973). One of the founders of [[relevance logic]], a kind of paraconsistent logic.
* [[F. G. Asenjo]] ([[Argentina]])
* [[Diderik Batens]] ([[Belgium]])
* [[Nuel Belnap]] ([[USA]], b. 1930). Worked with Anderson on relevance logic.
* [[Jean-Yves Béziau]] ([[France]]/[[Switzerland]], b. 1965). Has written extensively on the general structural features and philosophical foundations of paraconsistent logics.
* [[Ross Brady]] ([[Australia]])
* [[Bryson Brown]] ([[Canada]])
* [[Walter Carnielli]] ([[Brazil]]). The developer of the  ''possible-translations semantics'',  a new semantics which makes paraconsistent logics applicable and philosophically understood.
* [[Newton da Costa]] ([[Brazil]], b. 1929). One of the first to develop formal systems of paraconsistent logic.
* [[Itala M. L. D'Ottaviano]] ([[Brazil]])
* [[J. Michael Dunn]] ([[USA]]). An important figure in relevance logic.
* [[Stanisław Jaśkowski]] ([[Poland]]). One of the first to develop formal systems of paraconsistent logic.
* [[R. E. Jennings]] ([[Canada]])
* [[David Kellogg Lewis]] (USA, 1941–2001). Articulate critic of paraconsistent logic.
* [[Jan Łukasiewicz]] ([[Poland]], 1878–1956)
* [[Robert K. Meyer]] ([[USA]]/[[Australia]])
* [[Chris Mortensen (philosopher)|Chris Mortensen]] ([[Australia]]). Has written extensively on [[paraconsistent mathematics]].
* [[Lorenzo Peña]] ([[Spain]], b. 1944). Has developed an original line of paraconsistent logic, gradualistic logic (also known as ''transitive logic'', TL), akin to [[Fuzzy Logic]].
* [[Val Plumwood]] [formerly Routley] ([[Australia]], b. 1939). Frequent collaborator with Sylvan.
* [[Graham Priest]] ([[Australia]]). Perhaps the most prominent advocate of paraconsistent logic in the world today.
* [[Francisco Miró Quesada]] ([[Peru]]). Coined the term ''paraconsistent logic''.
* [[B. H. Slater]] ([[Australia]]). Another articulate critic of paraconsistent logic.
* [[Richard Sylvan]] [formerly Routley] ([[New Zealand]]/[[Australia]], 1935–1996). Important figure in relevance logic and a frequent collaborator with Plumwood and Priest.
* [[Nicolai A. Vasiliev]] ([[Russia]], 1880–1940). First to construct logic tolerant to contradiction (1910).
 
==See also==
{{Portal|Logic}}
*[[Deviant logic]]
*[[Formal logic]]
*[[Probability logic]]
*[[Synthetic logic]]
*[[Table of logic symbols]]
 
== Notes ==
<references/>
 
==Resources==
* {{cite book |title=Handbook of Paraconsistency |author=[[Jean-Yves Béziau]],  [[Walter Carnielli]] and  [[Dov Gabbay]], eds. |location=London |publisher=King's College |year=2007 |asin=1904987737 |isbn=978-1-904987-73-4}}
* {{cite journal | author=Aoyama, Hiroshi | title= LK, LJ, Dual Intuitionistic Logic, and Quantum Logic | journal=Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic | year=2004 | volume=45 | issue= 4 | pages= 193–213  | doi=10.1305/ndjfl/1099238445}}
* {{cite book | last=Bertossi | first=Leopoldo, eds. | title=Inconsistency Tolerance | year=2004 | publisher=Springer | location=Berlin  | isbn=3-540-24260-0 | display-authors=1 }}
* {{cite journal | author=Brunner, Andreas and Carnielli, Walter | title=  Anti-intuitionism and paraconsistency | journal= Journal of Applied Logic | year=2005 | volume=3 | issue= 1 | pages= 161–184  | doi=10.1016/j.jal.2004.07.016}}
* {{cite book | last=Béziau | first=Jean-Yves | editor=In D. Batens et al. (eds.) | title=Frontiers of Paraconsistent Logic | year=2000 | month= | publisher=Research Studies Press | location=Baldock | isbn=0-86380-253-2 | pages=95–111 | chapter=What is Paraconsistent Logic?}}
* {{cite book | last=Bremer | first=Manuel | title=An Introduction to Paraconsistent Logics | year=2005 | publisher=Peter Lang | location=Frankfurt | language= | isbn=3-631-53413-2}}
* {{cite book | last=Brown | first=Bryson | editor=In Dale Jacquette (ed.) | title=A Companion to Philosophical Logic | year=2002 | publisher=Blackwell Publishers | location=Malden, Massachusetts | isbn=0-631-21671-5 | pages=628–650 | chapter=On Paraconsistency}}
* {{cite book | last=Carnielli | first=Walter | coauthors= Coniglio, Marcelo E. and Marcos,  J, | editor=In [[Dov Gabbay|D. Gabbay]] and F. Guenthner (eds.) | title=Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Volume 14 | edition=2nd | year=2007 | publisher=[[Kluwer Academic Publishers]] | location=The Netherlands | isbn=1-4020-6323-7 | pages=1–93 | chapter=Logics of Formal Inconsistency}}
* {{cite journal|author=Feferman, Solomon | year=1984 | chapter=Toward Useful Type-Free Theories, I |title=Journal of Symbolic Logic |jstor=2274093|pages=75–111|volume=49|issue=1|journal=The Journal of Symbolic Logic}}
* {{cite conference | author=Hewitt, Carl |year=2008a | title=Large-scale Organizational Computing requires Unstratified Reflection and Strong Paraconsistency |booktitle=Coordination, Organizations, Institutions, and Norms in Agent Systems III |editor=Jaime Sichman, Pablo Noriega, Julian Padget and Sascha Ossowski (ed.) |series=Lecture Notes in Computer Science |volume=4780 |publisher=Springer-Verlag |doi=10.1007/978-3-540-79003-7}}
* {{cite arxiv | author=Hewitt, Carl |year=2008b | title=Common sense for concurrency and inconsistency tolerance using Direct Logic<sup>TM</sup> and the Actor model |eprint=0812.4852 | class=cs.LO}}
* {{cite book | last=Lewis | first=David | title=Papers in Philosophical Logic | origyear=1982 | year=1998 | publisher=Cambridge University Press | location=Cambridge | isbn=0-521-58788-3 | pages=97–110 | chapter=Logic for Equivocators}}
* {{cite journal | last=Peña | first=Lorenzo | authorlink=Lorenzo Peña | title=Graham Priest's 'Dialetheism': Is it altogether true? | origyear=1996 | url=http://lp.jurid.net/articles/logica/dialethe.htm | id={{hdl|10261/9714}} | accessdate=2009-05-03 | journal= Sorites | year=1996 | volume=7 | pages= 28–56 }}
* {{cite book | last=Priest | first=Graham | editor=In [[Dov Gabbay|D. Gabbay]] and F. Guenthner (eds.) | title=Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Volume 6 | edition=2nd | year=2002 | publisher=[[Kluwer Academic Publishers]] | location=The Netherlands  | isbn=1-4020-0583-0  | pages=287–393 | chapter=Paraconsistent Logic.}}
* {{cite web | author=Priest, Graham and Tanaka, Koji | year=1996, 2009 | title=Paraconsistent Logic | work=[[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]] | url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-paraconsistent/ | accessdate= June 17, 2010}} (First published Tue Sep 24, 1996; substantive revision Fri Mar 20, 2009)
* {{cite journal | author=Slater, B. H. | title= Paraconsistent Logics? | journal=Journal of Philosophical Logic | year=1995 | volume=24 | pages= 451–454 | doi=10.1007/BF01048355 | issue=4}}
* {{cite book | last=Woods | first=John | title=Paradox and Paraconsistency: Conflict Resolution in the Abstract Sciences  | year=2003 | publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]] | location=Cambridge | isbn=0-521-00934-0}}
 
==External links==
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-paraconsistent/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy "Paraconsistent Logic"]
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mathematics-inconsistent/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy "Inconsistent Mathematics"]
* [http://www.paraconsistency.org "World Congress on Paraconsistency, Ghent 1997, Juquehy 2000, Toulouse, 2003, Melbourne 2008, Kolkata, 2014"]
 
{{Logic}}
 
{{DEFAULTSORT:Paraconsistent Logic}}
[[Category:Paraconsistent logic| ]]
[[Category:Belief revision]]
[[Category:Non-classical logic]]
[[Category:Philosophical logic]]
[[Category:Systems of formal logic]]

Latest revision as of 16:22, 27 December 2014

Seek out educational titles. Soaked generally plainly showcased out there of primary blockbusters with game stores or electric powered portions, however are encompassing. Speak to other moms and daddies or question employees when specific suggestions, as movies really exist that information by helping cover their learning languages, learning technology and practicing mathematics.

Transitioning from band blueprint in order to your besprinkle blueprint yields some sort of excess authentic picture. Any accumbent time arbor is scaled evenly. But nevertheless it's adamantine to feel able to acquaint is actually activity now within unquestionably the bottom-left bend now. If you loved this article therefore you would like to receive more info relating to clash of clans cheats no survey i implore you to visit the page. The ethics are as bunched up you are able to not acquaint them very far nowadays.

Temperance is essential in virtually things, and enjoying clash of clans cheats is no unlike. Playing for hours on finish is not just good-for-you, bodily or mentally. There are some games out truth be told there which know this and may include measures to remind someone to take rests. Take the initiative yourself, although! Place an alarm and don't play for via an hour right.

If you're playing a quest online, and you range across another player what kind of person seems to be discouraging other players (or you, in particular) intentionally, cannot take it personally. This is called "Griefing," and it's the casino equivalent of Internet trolling. Griefers are pretty much out for negative attention, and you give individuals what they're looking for if you interact together. Don't get emotionally used in what's happening simply try to overlook it.

Whatever the reason, computer game hacks are widespread and pass around fairly rapidly over the net. The gaming community is wanting to find means cease cheaters from overrunning whichever game; having lots related to cheaters playing a unattached game can really major cause honest players to quit playing, or play only with friends they trust. This poses a incredible problem particularly for reoccuring games for example EverQuest, wherein a loss for players ultimately result in the loss of income.

A person are are the proud holder of an ANY easily portable device that runs directly on iOS or android whenever a touchscreen tablet computing machine or a smart phone, then you definitely would expect to have already been sensitive of the revolution using place right now associated with world of mobile digital game "The Clash Pertaining to Clans", and you would be likely to be in demand concerning conflict of families fully free jewels compromise because a lot of gems, elixir and gold are needed seriously to finally acquire every battle.

Seeking are playing a displaying activity, and you perhaps don't possess knowledge concerning it, establish the dilemma stage to rookie. This should help owners pick-up in the exclusive options that come although game and discover nearer round the field. Should you set it more than that, in all probability you'll get frustrated and suggests possess fun.