Three Prisoners problem: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
title of the mathematical games column
 
Line 1: Line 1:
{{about|pairwise comparisons in psychology|statistical analysis of paired comparisons|paired difference test}}
Nice to satisfy you, I am Marvella Shryock. Bookkeeping is her day occupation now. Years in the past we moved to North Dakota and I love every working day residing here. Doing ceramics is what her family and her appreciate.<br><br>Check out my weblog :: [http://forums.cellphonedge.com/groups/valuable-guidance-for-successfully-treating-candidiasis/ at home std test]
 
'''Pairwise comparison''' generally refers to any process of comparing entities in pairs to judge which of each entity is [[preference|preferred]], or has a greater amount of some [[quantitative property]]. The method of pairwise comparison is used in the scientific study of [[preference]]s, attitudes, [[voting systems]], [[social choice]], [[public choice]], and [[multiagent AI system]]s. In [[psychology]] literature, it is often referred to as '''paired comparison'''.
Prominent [[psychometrician]] [[L. L. Thurstone]] first introduced a scientific approach to using pairwise comparisons for measurement in 1927, which he referred to as the [[law of comparative judgment]]. Thurstone linked this approach to psychophysical theory developed by [[Ernst Heinrich Weber]] and [[Gustav Fechner]].  Thurstone demonstrated that the method can be used to order items along a dimension such as preference or importance using an interval-type scale.
 
==Overview==
If an individual or organization expresses a preference between two mutually distinct alternatives, this preference can be expressed as a pairwise comparison.  If the two alternatives are ''x'' and ''y'', the following are the possible pairwise comparisons:
 
The agent prefers ''x'' over ''y'': "''x''&nbsp;>&nbsp;''y''" or "''xPy''"
 
The agent prefers ''y'' over ''x'': "''y''&nbsp;>&nbsp;''x''" or "''yPx''"
 
The agent is indifferent between both alternatives: "''x''&nbsp;=&nbsp;''y''" or "''xIy''"
 
==Probabilistic models==
In terms of modern psychometric theory, [[Thurstone scale|Thurstone's approach]], called the law of comparative judgment, is more aptly regarded as a measurement model. The Bradley&ndash;Terry&ndash;Luce (BTL) model (Bradley & Terry, 1952; Luce, 1959) is often applied to pairwise comparison data to scale preferences. The BTL model is identical to Thurstone's model if the simple [[logistic function]] is used. Thurstone used the normal distribution in applications of the model. The simple logistic function varies by less than 0.01 from the cumulative normal [[ogive]] across the range, given an arbitrary scale factor.
 
In the BTL model, the probability that object ''j'' is judged to have more of an attribute than object ''i'' is:
 
: <math>
\Pr \{X_{ji}=1\} =\frac{e^{{\delta_j} - {\delta_i}}}{1 + e^{{\delta_j} - {\delta_i}}}
= \operatorname{logit}^{-1} (\delta_j - \delta_i),
</math>
 
where <math>\delta_i</math> is the scale location of object ''<math>i</math>''; <math>\operatorname{logit}^{-1}</math> is the [[logit|inverse logit]] function. For example, the scale location might represent the perceived quality of a product, or the perceived weight of an object.
 
The BTL is very closely related to the [[Rasch model]] for measurement.
 
Thurstone used the method of pairwise comparisons as an approach to measuring perceived intensity of physical stimuli, attitudes, preferences, choices, and values. He also studied implications of the theory he developed for opinion polls and political voting (Thurstone, 1959).
 
==Transitivity==
For a given decision agent, if the information, objective, and alternatives used by the agent remain constant, then it is generally assumed that pairwise comparisons over those alternatives by the decision agent are transitive.  Most agree upon what transitivity is, though there is debate about the transitivity of indifference. The rules of transitivity are as follows for a given decision agent.
 
If xPy and yPz, then xPz
 
If xPy and yIz, then xPz
 
If xIy and yPz, then xPz
 
If xIy and yIz, then xIz
 
This corresponds to (xPy or xIy) being a [[total preorder]], P being the corresponding [[strict weak order]], and I being the corresponding [[equivalence relation]].
 
Probabilistic models require transitivity only within the bounds of errors of estimates of scale locations of entities. Thus, decisions need not be deterministically transitive in order to apply probabilistic models. However, transitivity will generally hold for a large number of comparisons if models such as the BTL can be effectively applied.
 
Using Transitivity test<ref name = "Nikolic">Nikolić D (2012) Non-parametric detection of temporal order across pairwise measurements of time delays. ''Journal of Computational Neuroscience'', 22(1)" pp. 5–19.  http://www.danko-nikolic.com/wp-content/uploads/2011/09/Nikolic-Transitivity-2007.pdf</ref> one can investigate whether a data set of pairwise comparisons contains a higher degree of transitivity than expected by chance.
 
==Argument for intransitivity of indifference==
Some contend that indifference is not transitive.  Consider the following example.  Suppose you like apples and you prefer apples that are larger.  Now suppose there exists an apple A, an apple B, and an apple C which have identical intrinsic characteristics except for the following. Suppose B is larger than A, but it is not discernible without an extremely sensitive scale.  Further suppose C is larger than B, but this also is not discernible without an extremely sensitive scale.  However, the difference in sizes between apples A and C is large enough that you can discern that C is larger than A without a sensitive scale. In psychophysical terms, the size difference between A and C is above the [[just noticeable difference]] ('jnd') while the size differences between A and B and B and C are below the jnd.
 
You are confronted with the three apples in pairs without the benefit of a sensitive scale.  Therefore, when presented A and B alone, you are indifferent between apple A and apple B; and you are indifferent between apple B and apple C when presented B and C alone.  However, when the pair A and C are shown, you prefer C over A.
 
==Preference orders==
If pairwise comparisons are in fact transitive in respect to the four mentioned rules, then pairwise comparisons for a list of alternatives (''A''<sub>1</sub>,&nbsp;''A''<sub>2</sub>,&nbsp;''A''<sub>3</sub>,&nbsp;...,&nbsp;''A''<sub>''n''&minus;1</sub>, and ''A''<sub>''n''</sub>) can take the form:
 
: ''A''<sub>1</sub>(>[[XOR]]=)''A''<sub>2</sub>(>[[XOR]]=)''A''<sub>3</sub>(>[[XOR]]=)&nbsp;...&nbsp;(>[[XOR]]=)''A''<sub>''n''&minus;1</sub>(>[[XOR]]=)''A''<sub>''n''</sub>
 
For example, if there are three alternatives ''a'', ''b'', and ''c'', then the possible preference orders are:
 
*<math>a>b>c</math>
*<math>a>c>b</math>
*<math>b>a>c</math>
*<math>b>c>a</math>
*<math>c>a>b</math>
*<math>c>b>a</math>
*<math>a>b=c</math>
*<math>b=c>a</math>
*<math>b>a=c</math>
*<math>a=c>b</math>
*<math>c>a=b</math>
*<math>a=b>c</math>
*<math>a=b=c</math>
 
If the number of alternatives is n, and indifference is not allowed, then the number of possible preference orders for any given ''n''-value is&nbsp;''n''<nowiki>!</nowiki>.  If indifference is allowed, then the number of possible preference orders is the [[Strict_weak_ordering#The_number_of_total_preorders|number of total preorders]]. It can be expressed as a function of n:
 
: <math>\sum_{k=1}^n k! S_2(n,k),</math>
 
where ''S''<sub>2</sub>(''n'',&nbsp;''k'') is the [[Stirling number of the second kind]].
 
==Applications==
One important application of pairwise comparisons is the widely used [[Analytic Hierarchy Process]], a structured technique for helping people deal with complex decisions. It uses pairwise comparisons of tangible and intangible factors to construct ratio scales that are useful in making important decisions.<ref name='DMFL'>{{cite book | last = Saaty | first = Thomas L. | authorlink = | coauthors = | title = Decision Making for Leaders: The Analytic Hierarchy Process for Decisions in a Complex World | publisher = RWS Publications | date = 1999-05-01 | location = Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania | pages = | url = http://www.amazon.com/dp/096203178X | doi = | id = | isbn = 0-9620317-8-X }}</ref><ref name='RACSAM'>{{cite journal|title=Relative Measurement and its Generalization in Decision Making: Why Pairwise Comparisons are Central in Mathematics for the Measurement of Intangible Factors &ndash; The Analytic Hierarchy/Network Process|journal=[[Spanish Royal Academy of Sciences|Review of the Royal Academy of Exact, Physical and Natural Sciences, Series A: Mathematics (RACSAM)]]|date=2008-06|first=Thomas L.|last=Saaty|authorlink=Thomas L. Saaty|coauthors=|volume=102|issue=2|pages=251&ndash;318|id= |url=http://www.rac.es/ficheros/doc/00576.PDF|format=|accessdate=2008-12-22 }}</ref>
 
==See also==
*[[Law of comparative judgment]]
*[[Potentially all pairwise rankings of all possible alternatives]] (PAPRIKA) method
*[[PROMETHEE]] pairwise comparison method
*[[Preference (economics)]]
 
==References==
{{reflist}}
* {{SloanesRef |sequencenumber=A000142|name=Factorial numbers}}
* {{SloanesRef |sequencenumber=A000670|name=Number of preferential arrangements of n labeled elements}}
* Y. Chevaleyre, P.E. Dunne, U. Endriss, J. Lang, M. Lemaître, N. Maudet, J. Padget, S. Phelps, J.A. Rodríguez-Aguilar, and P. Sousa. Issues in Multiagent Resource Allocation. Informatica, 30:3&ndash;31, 2006.
 
==Further reading==
*Bradley, R.A. and Terry, M.E. (1952). Rank analysis of incomplete block designs, I. the method of paired comparisons. ''Biometrika'', 39, 324&ndash;345.
*David, H.A. (1988). The Method of Paired Comparisons. New York: Oxford University Press.
*Luce, R.D. (1959). ''Individual Choice Behaviours'': A Theoretical Analysis. New York: J. Wiley.
*Thurstone, L.L. (1927).  A law of comparative judgement. ''Psychological Review'', 34, 278&ndash;286.
*Thurstone, L.L. (1929).  ''The Measurement of Psychological Value''.  In T.V. Smith and W.K. Wright (Eds.), Essays in Philosophy by Seventeen Doctors of Philosophy of the University of Chicago.  Chicago: Open Court.
*Thurstone, L.L. (1959).  ''The Measurement of Values''.  Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
*Zermelo, E. (1928). ''[http://resolver.sub.uni-goettingen.de/purl?GDZPPN002370808 Die Berechnung der Turnier-Ergebnisse als ein Maximumproblem der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung]'', Mathematische Zeitschrift 29, 1929, S. 436–460
 
[[Category:Psychometrics]]

Latest revision as of 01:18, 22 October 2014

Nice to satisfy you, I am Marvella Shryock. Bookkeeping is her day occupation now. Years in the past we moved to North Dakota and I love every working day residing here. Doing ceramics is what her family and her appreciate.

Check out my weblog :: at home std test