Aptamer: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>Monkbot
en>Trappist the monk
Line 1: Line 1:
The '''secretary problem''' is one of many names for a famous problem of the [[optimal stopping]] theory. The problem has been studied extensively in the fields of [[applied probability]], [[statistics]], and [[decision theory]]. It is also known as the '''marriage problem''', the '''sultan's dowry problem''', the '''fussy suitor problem''', '''the googol game''', and the '''best choice problem'''.
Hi there. Allow me begin by introducing the author, her name is Myrtle Cleary. He used to be unemployed but now he is a pc operator but his marketing never arrives. What I adore doing is doing ceramics but I haven't made a dime with it. For a while she's been in South Dakota.<br><br>Look at my homepage [http://www.fit2dmax.com/fitcommunity/groups/useful-guidance-for-battling-your-candidiasis/ www.fit2dmax.com]
 
The basic form of the problem is the following: imagine an administrator willing to hire the best secretary out of <math>n</math> rankable applicants for a position. The applicants are interviewed one-by-one in random order. A decision about each particular applicant is to be made immediately after the interview. Once rejected, an applicant cannot be recalled. During the interview, the administrator can rank the applicant among all applicants interviewed so far, but is unaware of the quality of yet unseen applicants. The question is about the optimal strategy ([[stopping rule]]) to maximize the probability of selecting the best applicant. If the decision can be deferred to the end, this solved by the simple maximum [[selection algorithm]] of tracking the running maximum (and who achieved it), and selecting the overall maximum at the end. The difficulty is that the decision must be made immediately.
 
The problem has a strikingly elegant solution. The optimal stopping rule prescribes to reject  about <math>n/e</math> applicants after the interview (where ''e'' is the [[e (mathematical constant)|base of the natural logarithm]]) without choice then stop at the first applicant who is better than every applicant interviewed so far (or proceed to the last applicant if this never occurs).  Sometimes this strategy is called the <math>1/e</math> stopping rule, because the probability to stop at the best applicant with this strategy is about <math>1/e</math> already for moderate values of <math>n</math>. One reason why the secretary problem has received so much attention is that the optimal policy for the problem (the stopping rule) is simple, and selects the single best candidate about 37% of the time, irrespective of whether there are 100 or 100 million applicants. In fact, for any value of <math>n</math> the probability of selecting the best candidate when using the optimal policy is at least <math>1/e</math>.
 
==Formulation==
Although there are many variations, the basic problem can be stated as follows:
 
# There is a single secretarial position to fill.
# There are ''n'' applicants for the position, and the value of ''n'' is known.
# The applicants, if seen altogether, can be ranked from best to worst unambiguously.
# The applicants are interviewed sequentially in  random order, with each order being equally likely.
# Immediately after an interview, the interviewed applicant is either accepted or rejected, and the decision is irrevocable.
# The decision to accept or reject an applicant can be based only on the relative ranks of the applicants interviewed so far.
# The objective of the general solution is to have the highest probability of selecting the best applicant of the whole group.  This is the same as maximizing the expected payoff, with payoff defined to be one for the best applicant and zero otherwise.
 
Terminology: A ''candidate'' is defined as an applicant who, when interviewed, is better than all the applicants interviewed previously. ''Skip'' is used to mean "reject immediately after the interview".
 
Clearly, since the objective in the problem is to select the single best applicant, only candidates will be considered for acceptance. The "candidate" in this context corresponds to the concept of record in permutation.
 
==Deriving the optimal policy==
The optimal policy for the problem is a [[stopping rule]]. Under it, the interviewer rejects the first ''r''&nbsp;−&nbsp;1 applicants (let applicant ''M'' be the best applicant among these ''r''&nbsp;−&nbsp;1 applicants), and then selects the first subsequent applicant that is better than applicant ''M''. It can be shown that the optimal strategy lies in this class of strategies. For an arbitrary  cutoff ''r'', the probability that the best applicant is selected is
 
:<math>
\begin{align}
P(r)
&= \sum_{i=1}^{n}
P\left(\text{applicant } i \text{ is selected} | \text{applicant } i \text{ is the best}\right) \times
P\left(\text{applicant } i \text{ is the best}\right)
\\
&= \left[ \sum_{i=1}^{r-1} 0 \times \frac{1}{n} \right]
+ \left[ \sum_{i=r}^{n} P\left( \left.
\begin{array}{l}
\text{the second best of the first } i \text{ applicants} \\
\text{is in the first } r-1 \text{ applicants}
\end{array} \right|  \text{applicant } i \text{ is the best}
\right) \times \frac{1}{n} \right]
\\
&= \sum_{i=r}^{n} \frac{r-1}{i-1} \times \frac{1}{n}
\quad=\quad \frac{r-1}{n} \sum_{i=r}^{n} \frac{1}{i-1}.
\end{align}
</math>
 
This sum is obtained by noting that if applicant ''i'' is the best applicant, then it is selected if and only if the best applicant among the first ''i''&nbsp;−&nbsp;1 applicants is among the first ''r''&nbsp;−&nbsp;1 applicants that were rejected. Letting ''n'' tend to infinity, writing <math>x</math> as the limit of ''r''/''n'', using ''t'' for ''i''/''n'' and ''dt'' for 1/''n'', the sum can be approximated by the integral
 
:<math>
P(x)=x \int_{x}^{1}\frac{1}{t}\,dt = -x \log(x).
</math>
 
Taking the derivative of ''P''(''x'') with respect to <math>x</math>, setting it to 0, and solving for ''x'', we find that the optimal ''x'' is equal to 1/''e''.  Thus, the optimal cutoff tends to ''n''/''e'' as ''n'' increases, and the best applicant is selected with probability 1/''e''.
 
For small values of ''n'', the optimal ''r'' can also be obtained by standard [[dynamic programming]] methods. The optimal thresholds ''r'' and probability of selecting the best alternative ''P'' for several values of ''n'' are shown in the following table.
 
{| class="wikitable"
|-
! <math>n</math>
! 1
! 2
! 3
! 4
! 5
! 6
! 7
! 8
! 9
|-
| <math>r</math>
| 1
| 1
| 2
| 2
| 3
| 3
| 3
| 4
| 4
|-
| <math>P</math>
| 1.000
| 0.500
| 0.500
| 0.458
| 0.433
| 0.428
| 0.414
| 0.410
| 0.406
|}
 
The probability of selecting the best applicant in the classical secretary problem converges  toward <math>1/e\approx 0.368</math> {{OEIS|A068985}}.
 
==Alternative solution==
This problem and several modifications can be solved (including the proof of optimality) in a straightforward manner by the [[Odds algorithm]] (2000) which also allows for other applications. Modifications for the secretary problem which can be solved by this algorithm include random availabilities of applicants, more general hypotheses for applicants to be of interest to the decision maker, group interviews for applicants, as well as ''certain'' models for a random number of applicants. None of these modifications are treated in this article.
 
==Unknown number of applicants==
A major drawback for applications of the solution of the classical secretary problem is that the number of applicants <math> n </math> must be known in advance. One way to overcome this problem is to suppose that the number of applicants is a random variable <math>N </math> with a known distribution of  <math>P(N=k)_{k=1,2,\cdots} </math> (Presman and Sonin, 1972). For this model, the optimal solution is in general much harder, however. Moreover, the optimal success probability is now no longer around 1/e. Indeed, it is intuitive that there should be a price to pay for not knowing the number of applicants. However, in this model the price is high. Depending on the choice of the distribution of <math> N </math> the optimal win probability is typically much lower than 1/e, and may even approach zero. Looking for ways to cope with this new problem led to the following approach and result:
 
===1/e-law of best choice===
The essence of the model is based on the idea that real-world problems pose themselves in real time and that it is easier to estimate times in which specific events (arrivals of applicants) should occur more likely (if they do) than to estimate the distribution of the number of specific events which will occur. This idea led to the following approach, the so-called '''Unified approach'''(1984):
 
'''The model''': An applicant must be selected on some time interval <math>[0,T]</math> from an unknown number <math> N</math> of rankable applicants. The goal is to maximize the probability of selecting online the best under the hypothesis that all arrival orders of different ranks are equally likely. Suppose that all applicants have independently of each other the same arrival time density <math>f</math> on <math>[0,T]</math> and let  <math>F</math> denote the corresponding arrival time distribution function, that is
 
: <math>F(t) = \int_{0}^{t} f(s)ds </math>, <math>\, 0\le t\le T</math>.
 
'''1/e-law''':  Let <math>\tau</math> be such that <math> F(\tau)=1/e.</math> Consider the strategy to wait and observe all applicants up to time <math>\tau </math> and then to select, if possible, the first candidate after time <math>\tau </math> which is better than all preceding ones. Then this strategy, called ''1/e-strategy'', has the following properties:
 
The ''1/e-strategy''
 
:(i)  yields for all <math>N</math> a success probability of at least 1/e,
 
:(ii) is the unique strategy guaranteeing this lower success probability bound 1/e, and the bound is optimal,
 
:(iii) selects, if there is at least one applicant, none at all with probability exactly 1/e.
 
When the 1/e-law was discovered in 1984 it came as a surprise. The reason was that a value of about 1/e had been considered before as being out of reach in a model for unknown <math> N </math>, whereas now this value was achieved as a lower bound, and this in a model with arguably weaker hypotheses (see e.g. Math. Reviews 85:m).
 
This law is sometimes confused with the solution for the secretary problem because of the similar role of the number 1/e.  Note however, that in the 1/e-law, this role is stronger and more general. The result is also stronger, since it holds for an '''unknown''' number of applicants and since the model is more tractable for applications.
 
==The Game of Googol==
According to {{harvnb|Ferguson|1989}} the Secretary Problem appeared for the first time in print in [[Martin Gardner]]'s column of Scientific American  in 1960. Here is how Martin Gardner formulated the problem: "Ask someone to take as many slips of paper as he pleases, and on each slip write a different positive number. The numbers may range from small fractions of 1 to a number the size of a ''googol'' (1 followed by a hundred 0s) or even larger. These slips are turned face down and shuffled over the top of a table. One at a time you turn the slips face up. The aim is to stop turning when you come to the number that you guess to be the largest of the series. You cannot go back and pick a previously turned slip. If you turn over all the slips, then of course you must pick the last one turned."
 
In the paper "Who solved the Secretary problem?" {{harvnb|Ferguson|1989}} pointed out that the Secretary Problem remained unsolved as it was stated by M. Gardner, that is as a two-person [[zero-sum game]] with two antagonistic players. In this game Alice, the informed player, writes secretly distinct numbers on <math>n</math> cards. Bob,  the stopping player, observes the actual values and can stop turning cards whenever he wants, winning if the last card turned has the overall maximum number. The difference with the basic Secretary Problem is that Bob observes the actual values written on the cards which he can use in his decision procedures. The numbers on cards are analogous to the numerical qualities of applicants in some versions of the Secretary Problem. The joint probability distribution of the numbers is under the control of Alice.
 
Bob wants to guess the maximum number with highest possible probability, while Alice' goal is to keep this probability as low as possible. It is not optimal for Alice to sample the numbers independently from some fixed distribution, and she can play better by choosing random numbers in some dependent way. For <math>n=2</math> Alice has no minimax strategy, which is closely related to a paradox of T. Cover. But for <math>n>2</math> the game has a solution: Alice can choose random numbers (which are dependent random variables) in such a way  that Bob cannot play better than using the classical stopping strategy based on the relative ranks ({{harvnb|Gnedin|1994}}).
 
==Heuristic performance==
The remainder of the article deals again with the secretary problem for a known number of applicants.
 
[[Image:SecretaryProblemHeuristicPlot.png|thumb|Expected success probabilities for three heuristics.|300px|right|Expected success probabilities for three heuristics.]]
 
{{harvnb|Stein|Seale|Rapoport|2003}} derived the expected success probabilities for several psychologically plausible heuristics that might be employed in the secretary problem. The heuristics they examined were:
* '''The cutoff rule (CR):''' Do not accept any of the first ''y'' applicants; thereafter, select the first encountered candidate (i.e., an applicant with relative rank 1). This rule has as a special case the optimal policy for the classical secretary problem for which ''y''&nbsp;=&nbsp;''r''.
* '''Candidate count rule (CCR):''' Select the ''y'' encountered candidate. Note, that this rule does not necessarily skip any applicants; it only considers how many candidates have been observed, not how deep the decision maker is in the applicant sequence.
* '''Successive non-candidate rule (SNCR):''' Select the first encountered candidate after observing ''y'' non-candidates (i.e., applicants with relative rank&nbsp;>&nbsp;1).
 
Note that each heuristic has a single parameter ''y''. The figure (shown on right) displays the expected success probabilities for each heuristic as a function of ''y'' for problems with ''n''&nbsp;=&nbsp;80.
 
==Cardinal payoff variant==
Finding the single best applicant might seem like a rather strict objective. One can imagine that the interviewer would rather hire a higher-valued applicant than a lower-valued one, and not only be concerned with getting the best. That is, he will derive some value from selecting an applicant that is not necessarily the best, and the value he derives is increasing in the value of the one he selects.
 
To model this problem, suppose that the <math>n</math> applicants have "true" values that are [[random variable]]s ''X'' drawn [[i.i.d.]] from a [[Uniform distribution (continuous)|uniform distribution]] on [0,&nbsp;1]. Similar to the classical problem described above, the interviewer only observes whether each applicant is the best so far (a candidate), must accept or reject each on the spot, and ''must'' accept the last one if he is reached. (To be clear, the interviewer does not learn the actual relative rank of ''each'' applicant. He learns only whether the applicant has relative rank 1.) However, in this version his ''payoff'' is given by the true value of the selected applicant. For example, if he selects an applicant whose true value is 0.8, then he will earn 0.8. The interviewer's objective is to maximize the expected value of the selected applicant.
 
Since the applicant's values are i.i.d. draws from a uniform distribution on [0,&nbsp;1], the [[expected value]] of the ''t''th applicant given that <math>x_{t}=\max\left\{x_1, x_2, \ldots, x_t\right\}</math> is given by
 
:<math>
E_{t}=E\left(X_{t}|I_{t}=1\right)=\frac{t}{t+1}.
</math>
 
As in the classical problem, the optimal policy is given by a threshold, which for this problem we will denote by <math>c</math>, at which the interviewer should begin accepting candidates. {{harvnb|Bearden|2006}} showed that ''c'' is either <math>\lfloor \sqrt n \rfloor</math> or <math>\lceil \sqrt n \rceil</math>. (In fact, whichever is closest to <math> \sqrt n </math>.) This follows from the fact that given a problem with <math>n</math> applicants, the expected payoff for some arbitrary threshold 1&nbsp;=&nbsp;''c''&nbsp;=&nbsp;''n'' is
 
:<math>
V_{n}(c)=\sum_{t=c}^{n-1}\left[\prod_{s=c}^{t-1}\left(\frac{s-1}{s}\right)\right]\left(\frac{1}{t+1}\right)
+\left[\prod_{s=c}^{n-1}\left(\frac{s-1}{s}\right)\right]\frac{1}{2}={\frac {2cn-{c}^{2}+c-n}{2cn}}.
</math>
 
Differentiating <math> V_{n}(c)</math> with respect to ''c'', one gets
 
: <math>\frac{\partial V}{\partial c} = \frac{ -{c}^{\,2}+n }{ 2{c}^{\,2}n }.</math>
 
Since <math>\partial^{\,2}V / \partial c^{\,2}<0</math> for all permissible values of <math>c</math>, we find that <math>V</math> is maximized at <math>c=\sqrt n</math>. Since ''V'' is convex in <math>c</math>, the optimal integer-valued threshold must be either <math>\lfloor \sqrt n \rfloor</math> or <math>\lceil \sqrt n \rceil</math>. Thus, for most values of <math>n</math> the interviewer will begin accepting applicants sooner in the cardinal payoff version than in the classical version where the objective is to select the single best applicant. Note that this is not an asymptotic result: It holds for all <math>n</math>.
 
 
==Other Modifications==
There are at least two variants of the secretary problem that also have simple and elegant solutions.
 
One variant replaces the desire to pick the best with the desire to pick the second-best.  [[Robert J. Vanderbei]] calls this the "postdoc" problem arguing that the "best" will go to Harvard.  For this problem, the probability of success for an even number of applicants is exactly <math> \frac{0.25n^2}{n(n-1)}. </math>. This probability tends to 1/4 as n tends to infinity illustrating the fact that it is easier to pick the best than the second-best.
 
For a second variant, the number of selections is specified to be greater than
one.  In other words, the interviewer is not hiring just one secretary but
rather is, say, admitting a class of students from an applicant pool.  Under the
assumption that success is achieved if and only if all the selected candidates
are superior to all of the not-selected candidates, it is again a problem that
can be solved.  It was shown in {{harvnb|Vanderbei|1980}} that when n is
even and the desire is to select exactly half the candidates, the optimal
strategy yields a success probability of <math>\frac{1}{n/2+1}</math>.
 
 
==Experimental studies==
Experimental [[Experimental psychology|psychologists]] and [[experimental economics|economists]] have studied the [[Decision making|decision behavior]] of actual people in secretary problem situations.<ref>Bearden, Murphy, and Rapoport, 2006; Bearden, Rapoport, and Murphy, 2006; Seale and Rapoport, 1997</ref> In large part, this work has shown that people tend to stop searching too soon. This may be explained, at least in part, by the cost of evaluating candidates. In real world settings, this might suggest that people do not search enough whenever they are faced with problems where the decision alternatives are encountered sequentially. For example, when trying to decide at which gas station to stop for gas, people might not search enough before stopping. If true, then they would tend to pay more for gas than they might had they searched longer. The same may be true when people search online for airline tickets. Experimental research on problems such as the secretary problem is sometimes referred to as [[behavioral operations research]].
 
==Neural Correlates==
While there is a substantial body of [[neuroscience]] research on information integration, or the representation of belief, in perceptual decision-making tasks using both animal <ref>{{cite journal|last=Shadlen|first=M.|coauthors=Newsome, B.|title=Motion perception: seeing and deciding|journal=Proc Natl Acad Sci USA|year=1996|volume=93|pages=628–633}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal|last=Roitman|first=J.D.|coauthors=Shadlen, M.N.|title=Response of neurons in the lateral intraparietal area during a combined visual discrimination reaction time task|journal=J Neurosci|year=2002|volume=22|pages=9475–9489.}}</ref> and human subjects,<ref>{{cite journal|last=Heekeren|first=H.R.|coauthors=Marrett, S; Ungerleider, L.G.|title=The neural systems that mediate human perceptual decision making|journal=Nat Rev Neurosci|year=2008|volume=9|pages=467–479}}</ref> there is relatively little known about how the decision to stop gathering information is arrived at.
 
Researchers have studied the neural bases of solving the secretary problem in healthy volunteers using [[functional MRI]].<ref>{{cite journal|last=Costa|first=V.D.|coauthors=Averbeck, B.B.|title=Frontal–Parietal and Limbic-Striatal Activity Underlies Information Sampling in the Best Choice Problem|journal=Cerebral Cortex|year=2013|doi=10.1093/cercor/bht286}}</ref> A [[Markov decision process]] (MDP) was used to quantify the value of continuing to search versus committing to the current option. Decisions to take versus decline an option engaged [[parietal cortex|parietal]] and [[dorsolateral prefrontal cortex|dorsolateral prefrontal]] cortices, as well [[ventral striatum]], [[Insular cortex|anterior insula]], and [[anterior cingulate]]. Therefore, brain regions previously implicated in evidence integration and [[Reward system|reward]] representation encode threshold crossings that trigger decisions to commit to a choice.
 
==History==
The secretary problem was apparently introduced in 1949 by [[Merrill M. Flood]], who called it the fiancée problem in a lecture he gave that year. He referred to it several times during the 1950s, for example in a conference talk at [[Purdue University|Purdue]] on 9 May 1958, and it eventually became widely known in the folklore although nothing was published at the time. In 1958 he sent a letter to [[Leonard Gillman]], with copies to a dozen friends including [[Samuel Karlin]] and J. Robbins, outlining a proof of the optimum strategy, with an appendix by R. Palermo who proved that all strategies are dominated by a strategy of the form "reject the first p unconditionally, then accept the next candidate". (See Flood (1958).)
 
The first publication was apparently by [[Martin Gardner]] in Scientific American, February 1960. He had heard about it from John H. Fox, Jr., and L. Gerald Marnie, who had independently come up with an equivalent problem in 1958; they called it the "game of Googol". Fox and Marnie did not know the optimum solution; Gardner asked for advice from [[Leo Moser]], who (together with J. R. Pounder) provided a correct analysis for publication in the magazine. Soon afterwards, several mathematicians wrote to Gardner to tell him about the equivalent problem they had heard via the grapevine, all of which can most likely be traced to Flood's original work.
 
The ''1/e-law'' is due to [[F. Thomas Bruss]] (1984).
 
Ferguson (1989) has an extensive bibliography, and points out that a similar (but different) problem had been considered by [[Arthur Cayley]] in 1875 and even by [[Johannes Kepler]] long before that.
 
==See also==
* [[Optimal stopping]]
* [[Odds algorithm]]
* [[Robbins' problem]]
* [[Search theory]]
* [[Dating]]
 
==References==
{{Refbegin}}
* {{Cite journal|last=Bearden |first=J.N. |title=A new secretary problem with rank-based selection and cardinal payoffs |journal=Journal of Mathematical Psychology |volume=50 |pages=58–9 |year=2006 |doi=10.1016/j.jmp.2005.11.003 |ref=harv}}
* {{Cite journal|author=Bearden, J.N., Murphy, R.O. Rapoport, A. |title=A multi-attribute extension of the secretary problem: Theory and experiments |journal=Journal of Mathematical Psychology |volume=49 |pages=410–425 |year=2005 |doi=10.1016/j.jmp.2005.08.002|issue=5 }}
* {{Cite journal|author=Bearden, J.N., Rapoport, A., Murphy R.O. |title=Sequential observation and selection with rank-dependent payoffs: An experimental test |journal=Management Science |volume=52 |pages=1437–49 |year=2006 |doi=10.1287/mnsc.1060.0535|issue=9 }}
* {{Cite journal|author=F. Thomas Bruss |authorlink=F. Thomas Bruss |title=A unified Approach to a Class of Best Choice problems with an Unknown Number of Options |journal=Annals of Probability |volume=12 |pages=882–891 |year=1984 |doi=10.1214/aop/1176993237|issue=3 }}
* {{Cite journal|author=F. Thomas Bruss |title=Sum the odds to one and stop |journal=Annals of Probability |volume=28 |pages=1384–91 |year=2000 |doi=10.1214/aop/1019160340|issue=3 }}
* {{Cite journal|last=Ferguson|first=T.S.<ref>A mathematics professor at [[UCLA]] and the father of [[Chris Ferguson|Chris "Jesus" Ferguson]], the professional poker player</ref> |title=Who solved the secretary problem? |journal=Statistical Science |volume=4 |pages=282–296 |year=1989 |
doi=10.1214/ss/1177012493|issue=3 }}
* {{Cite journal|last=Gnedin|first=A.|title=A solution to the game of Googol  |journal=Annals of Probability |volume=22 |pages=1588–1595  |year=1994 |doi=10.1214/aop/1176988613|issue=3 }}
* {{Cite journal|doi=10.2307/1402748 |author=Freeman, P.R. |title=The secretary problem and its extensions: A review |journal=International Statistical Review / Revue Internationale de Statistique |volume=51 |issue=2 |pages=189–206 |year=1983 |jstor=1402748 }}
* Hill, T.P. "[http://www.americanscientist.org/issues/feature/2009/2/knowing-when-to-stop/1 Knowing When to Stop]". ''American Scientist'', Vol. 97, 126-133 (2009). (For French translation, see [http://www.pourlascience.fr/ewb_pages/f/fiche-article-savoir-quand-s-arreter-22670.php cover story] in the July issue of ''Pour la Science'' (2009))
* {{Cite journal|author=Seale, D.A., Rapoport, A. |title=Sequential decision making with relative ranks: An experimental investigation of the 'secretary problem' |journal=Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes |volume=69 |pages=221–236 |year=1997 |doi=10.1006/obhd.1997.2683|issue=3 }}
* {{Cite journal|last1=Stein |first1=W.E. |last2=Seale |first2=D.A. |last3=Rapoport |first3=A. |title=Analysis of heuristic solutions to the best choice problem |journal=European Journal of Operational Research |volume=151 |pages=140–152 |year= 2003|doi=10.1016/S0377-2217(02)00601-X |ref=harv}}
* Merrill R. Flood, letter written in 1958, a copy of which can be found in the Martin Gardner papers at Stanford University Archives, series 1, box 5, folder 19.
* [[Martin Gardner]], New Mathematical Diversions from Scientific American. Simon and Schuster, 1966, Chapter 3, Problem 3 [reprints his original column published in February 1960 with additional comments].
* {{Cite book|author=Miller, Geoffrey F. |title=The mating mind: how sexual choice shaped the evolution of human nature |publisher=Anchor Books |year=2001 |isbn=0-385-49517-X }}
* ''Framing Our Thoughts: Ecological Rationality as Evolutionary Psychology's Answer to the Frame Problem'', Timothy Ketelaar and Peter M. Todd, Chapter 5 of ''Conceptual Challenges in Evolutionary Psychology'', p.&nbsp;187.
* {{Cite journal|author=Sardelis, D., Valahas, T. |title=Decision Making: A Golden Rule |journal=American Mathematical Monthly |volume=99 |issue=3 |pages=935–942 |date=March 1992 }}
*{{Cite journal|author = Robert J. Vanderbei,|title = The Optimal Choice of a Subset of a Population| journal = Mathematics of Operations Research| volume = 5 | issue = 4| pages=481-486|year = 1980|ref = harv}}
* [[Robert J. Vanderbei]] "[http://www.princeton.edu/~rvdb/tex/PostdocProblem/PostdocProb.pdf The Postdoc Variant of the Secretary Problem]"
 
==Notes==
{{Reflist}}
 
==External links==
* [http://www.utilitymill.com/utility/Secretary_Problem_Optimizer Online Utility to Calculate Optimal r]
* {{OEIS|A054404}} List of optimal r
* {{MathWorld | urlname=SultansDowryProblem | title=Sultan's Dowry Problem}}
* {{cite web|url=http://www.spotlightmind.com/optimal-search |author= Neil Bearden | title = Optimal Search (Secretary Problems)}}
* [http://www.math.ucla.edu/~tom/Stopping/Contents.html Optimal Stopping and Applications book by Thomas S. Ferguson]
* [http://www.mathpages.com/home/kmath018/kmath018.htm Optimizing Your Wife] at MathPages
{{Use dmy dates|date=September 2010}}
 
{{DEFAULTSORT:Secretary Problem}}
[[Category:Decision theory]]
[[Category:Sequential methods]]
[[Category:Optimal decisions]]
[[Category:Named probability problems]]

Revision as of 02:37, 1 March 2014

Hi there. Allow me begin by introducing the author, her name is Myrtle Cleary. He used to be unemployed but now he is a pc operator but his marketing never arrives. What I adore doing is doing ceramics but I haven't made a dime with it. For a while she's been in South Dakota.

Look at my homepage www.fit2dmax.com