Octal: Difference between revisions
en>Elphion restore version of 29 July 2012 |
en>DemocraticLuntz m Reverted 1 edit by 76.110.253.151 identified as test/vandalism using STiki |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
= | {{Bots|deny=AWB}} | ||
In [[mathematics]], an '''ordered pair''' (''a'', ''b'') is a pair of [[mathematical object]]s. The order in which the objects appear in the pair is significant: the ordered pair (''a'', ''b'') is different from the ordered pair (''b'', ''a'') unless ''a'' = ''b''. (In contrast, the [[unordered pair]] {''a'', ''b''} equals the unordered pair {''b'', ''a''}.) | |||
Ordered pairs are also called [[tuple|2-tuples]], or [[sequence]]s of length 2; ordered pairs of [[scalar (mathematics)|scalars]] are also called 2-dimensional [[Vector (mathematics and physics)|vectors]]. | |||
The entries of an ordered pair can be other ordered pairs, enabling the recursive definition of ordered [[n-tuple|''n''-tuple]]s (ordered lists of ''n'' objects). For example, the ordered triple (''a'',''b'',''c'') can be defined as (''a'', (''b'',''c'')), i.e., as one pair nested in another. | |||
< | |||
In the ordered pair (''a'', ''b''), the object ''a'' is called the ''first entry'', and the object ''b'' the ''second entry'' of the pair. Alternatively, the objects are called the first and second ''coordinates'', or the left and right ''projections'' of the ordered pair. | |||
[[Cartesian product]]s and [[binary relations]] (and hence [[function (mathematics)|functions]]) are defined in terms of ordered pairs. | |||
==Generalities== | |||
Let <math>(a_1, b_1)</math> and <math>(a_2, b_2)</math> be ordered pairs. Then the '''characteristic''' (or ''defining'') '''property''' of the ordered pair is: | |||
</ | :<math>(a_1, b_1) = (a_2, b_2)\quad\text{if and only if}\quad a_1 = a_2\text{ and }b_1 = b_2.\!</math> | ||
The [[Set (mathematics)|set]] of all ordered pairs whose first entry is in some set ''A'' and whose second entry is in some set ''B'' is called the [[Cartesian product]] of ''A'' and ''B'', and written ''A'' × ''B''. A [[binary relation]] between sets ''A'' and ''B'' is a [[subset]] of ''A'' × ''B''. | |||
If one wishes to employ the <math>\ (a,b)</math> notation for a different purpose (such as denoting [[open interval]]s on the [[real number line]]) the ordered pair may be denoted by the variant notation <math>\left \langle a,b\right \rangle.</math> | |||
The left and right projection of a pair ''p'' is usually denoted by ''π''<sub>1</sub>(''p'') and ''π''<sub>2</sub>(''p''), or by ''π''<sub>''l''</sub>(''p'') and ''π''<sub>''r''</sub>(''p''), respectively. | |||
In contexts where arbitrary ''n''-tuples are considered, ''π''<sup>''n''</sup><sub>''i''</sub>(''t'')<!---how to get the subscript exactly below the superscript?---> is a common notation for the ''i''-th component of an ''n'' tuple ''t''. | |||
==Defining the ordered pair using set theory== | |||
The above characteristic property of ordered pairs is all that is required to understand the role of ordered pairs in mathematics. Hence the ordered pair can be taken as a [[primitive notion]], whose associated axiom is the characteristic property. This was the approach taken by the [[Bourbaki|N. Bourbaki]] group in its ''Theory of Sets'', published in 1954, long after Kuratowski discovered his reduction (below). The Kuratowski definition was added in the second edition of ''Theory of Sets'', published in 1970. | |||
If one agrees that [[set theory]] is an appealing [[foundations of mathematics|foundation of mathematics]], then all mathematical objects must be defined as [[Set (mathematics)|sets]] of some sort. Hence if the ordered pair is not taken as primitive, it must be defined as a set.<ref>Quine has argued that the set-theoretical implementations of the concept of the ordered pair is a paradigm for the clarification of philosophical ideas (see "Word and Object", section 53). | |||
The general notion of such definitions or implementations are discussed in Thomas Forster "Reasoning about theoretical entities". | |||
</ref> Several set-theoretic definitions of the ordered pair are given below. | |||
===Wiener's definition=== | |||
[[Norbert Wiener]] proposed the first set theoretical definition of the ordered pair in 1914:<ref>Wiener's paper "A Simplification of the logic of relations" is reprinted, together with a valuable commentary on pages 224ff in van Heijenoort, Jean (1967), ''From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1979-1931'', Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA, ISBN 0-674-32449-8 (pbk.). van Heijenoort states the simplification this way: "By giving a definition of the ordered pair of two elements in terms of class operations, the note reduced the theory of relations to that of classes".</ref> | |||
:<math>\left( a, b \right) := | |||
\left\{\left\{ \left\{a\right\},\, \emptyset \right\},\, \left\{\left\{b\right\}\right\}\right\}.</math> | |||
He observed that this definition made it possible to define the [[type theory|types]] of ''[[Principia Mathematica]]'' as sets. ''Principia Mathematica'' had taken types, and hence [[relation (mathematics)|relations]] of all arities, as [[primitive notion|primitive]]. | |||
Wiener used <nowiki>{{</nowiki>''b''}} instead of {''b''} to make the definition compatible with [[type theory]] where all elements in a class must be of the same "type". With nesting ''b'' within an additional set its type is made equal to <math>\{\{a\}, \emptyset\}</math>'s. | |||
===Hausdorff's definition=== | |||
About the same time as Wiener (1914), [[Felix Hausdorff]] proposed his definition: | |||
: <math>(a, b) := \left\{ \{a, 1\}, \{b, 2\} \right\}</math> | |||
"where 1 and 2 are two distinct objects different from a and b."<ref>cf introduction to Wiener's paper in van Heijenoort 1967:224</ref> | |||
===Kuratowski definition=== | |||
In 1921 [[Kazimierz Kuratowski]] offered the now-accepted definition<ref>cf introduction to Wiener's paper in van Heijenoort 1967:224. van Heijenoort observes that the resulting set that represents the ordered pair "has a type higher by 2 than the elements (when they are of the same type)"; he offers references that show how, under certain circumstances, the type can be reduced to 1 or 0.</ref><ref>{{cite journal|title=Sur la notion de l'ordre dans la Théorie des Ensembles|first=Casimir|last=Kuratowski|authorlink=Kazimierz Kuratowski|year=1921|journal=[[Fundamenta Mathematicae]]|pages=161–171|volume=2|number=1|url=http://matwbn.icm.edu.pl/ksiazki/fm/fm2/fm2122.pdf}}</ref> | |||
of the ordered pair (''a'', ''b''): | |||
:<math>(a, \ b)_K \; := \ \{ \{ a \}, \ \{ a, \ b \} \}.</math> | |||
Note that this definition is used even when the first and the second coordinates are identical: | |||
: <math>(x,\ x)_K = \{\{x\},\{x, \ x\}\} = \{\{x\},\ \{x\}\} = \{\{x\}\}</math> | |||
Given some ordered pair ''p'', the property "''x'' is the first coordinate of ''p''" can be formulated as: | |||
:<math>\forall{Y}{\in}{p}:{x}{\in}{Y}.</math> | |||
The property "''x'' is the second coordinate of ''p''" can be formulated as: | |||
:<math>(\exist{Y}{\in}{p}:{x}{\in}{Y})\and(\forall{Y_{1},Y_{2}}{\in}{p}:Y_{1}\ne Y_{2}\rarr ({x}{\notin}{Y_{1}}\or{x}{\notin}{Y_{2}})).</math> | |||
In the case that the left and right coordinates are identical, the right [[conjunct]] <math>(\forall{Y_{1},Y_{2}}{\in}{p}:Y_{1}\ne Y_{2}\rarr ({x}{\notin}{Y_{1}}\or{x}{\notin}{Y_{2}}))</math> is trivially true, since ''Y''<sub>1</sub> ≠ ''Y''<sub>2</sub> is never the case. | |||
This is how we can extract the first coordinate of a pair (using the notation for [[Intersection_(set_theory)#Arbitrary_intersections|arbitrary intersection]] and [[Union_(set_theory)#Arbitrary_unions|arbitrary union]]): | |||
:<math>\pi_1(p) = \bigcup\bigcap p</math> | |||
This is how the second coordinate can be extracted: | |||
:<math>\pi_2(p) = \bigcup\{x \in \bigcup p \mid \bigcup p \not= \bigcap p \rarr x \notin \bigcap p \}</math> | |||
==== Variants ==== | |||
The above Kuratowski definition of the ordered pair is "adequate" in that it satisfies the characteristic property that an ordered pair must satisfy, namely that <math>(a,b) = (x,y) \leftrightarrow (a=x) \and (b=y)</math>. In particular, it adequately expresses 'order', in that <math>(a,b) = (b,a)</math> is not necessarily true. There are other definitions, of similar or lesser complexity, that are equally adequate: | |||
* <math>( a, b )_{\text{reverse}} := \{ \{ b \}, \{a, b\}\};</math> | |||
* <math>( a, b )_{\text{short}} := \{ a, \{a, b\}\};</math> | |||
* <math>( a, b )_{\text{01}} := \{\{0, a \}, \{1, b \}\}.</math>{{clarify|reason=This definition seems to be quite similar to Hausdorff's definition explained above. Unless there is a particular reason (which then should be made explicit here), it should be omitted here.|date=July 2013}} | |||
The '''reverse''' definition is merely a trivial variant of the Kuratowski definition, and as such is of no independent interest. The definition '''short''' is so-called because it requires two rather than three pairs of [[bracket|braces]]. Proving that '''short''' satisfies the characteristic property requires the [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory]] [[axiom of regularity]].<ref>Tourlakis, George (2003) ''Lectures in Logic and Set Theory. Vol. 2: Set Theory''. Cambridge Univ. Press. Proposition III.10.1.</ref> Moreover, if one accepts the [[Natural_number#A_standard_construction|standard set-theoretic construction of the natural numbers]], then 2 is defined as the set {0, 1} = {0, {0}}, which is indistinguishable from the pair (0, 0)<sub>short</sub>. Yet another disadvantage of the '''short''' pair is the fact, that even if ''a'' and ''b'' are of the same type, the elements of the '''short''' pair are not. (However, if ''a'' = ''b'' then the '''short''' version keeps having cardinality 2, which is something one might expect of any "pair", including any "ordered pair". Also note that the '''short''' version is used in [[Tarski–Grothendieck set theory]], upon which the [[Mizar system]] is founded.) | |||
====Proving that definitions satisfy the characteristic property==== | |||
Prove: (''a'', ''b'') = (''c'', ''d'') [[if and only if]] ''a'' = ''c'' and ''b'' = ''d''. | |||
'''Kuratowski''':<br> | |||
''If''. If ''a = c'' and ''b = d'', then {{''a''}, {''a, b''}} = {{''c''}, {''c, d''}}. Thus (''a, b'')<sub>K</sub> = (''c, d'')<sub>K</sub>. | |||
''Only if''. Two cases: ''a'' = ''b'', and ''a'' ≠ ''b''. | |||
If ''a'' = ''b'': | |||
:(''a, b'')<sub>K</sub> = {{''a''}, {''a, b''}} = {{''a''}, {''a, a''}} = <nowiki>{{</nowiki>''a''}}. | |||
:(''c, d'')<sub>K</sub> = {{''c''}, {''c, d''}} = <nowiki>{{</nowiki>''a''}}. | |||
:Thus {''c''} = {''c, d''} = {''a''}, which implies ''a'' = ''c'' and ''a'' = ''d''. By hypothesis, ''a'' = ''b''. Hence ''b'' = ''d''. | |||
If ''a'' ≠ ''b'', then (''a, b'')<sub>K</sub> = (''c, d'')<sub>K</sub> implies {{''a''}, {''a, b''}} = {{''c''}, {''c, d''}}. | |||
:Suppose {''c, d''} = {''a''}. Then ''c = d = a'', and so {{''c''}, {''c, d''}} = {{''a''}, {''a, a''}} = {{''a''}, {''a''}} = <nowiki>{{</nowiki>''a''}}. But then {{''a''}, {''a, b''}} would also equal <nowiki>{{</nowiki>''a''}}, so that ''b = a'' which contradicts ''a'' ≠ ''b''. | |||
:Suppose {''c''} = {''a, b''}. Then ''a = b = c'', which also contradicts ''a'' ≠ ''b''. | |||
:Therefore {''c''} = {''a''}, so that ''c = a'' and {''c, d''} = {''a, b''}. | |||
:If ''d = a'' were true, then {''c, d''} = {''a, a''} = {''a''} ≠ {''a, b''}, a contradiction. Thus ''d = b'' is the case, so that ''a = c'' and ''b = d''. | |||
'''Reverse''':<br> | |||
(''a, b'')<sub>reverse</sub> = {{''b''}, {''a, b''}} = {{''b''}, {''b, a''}} = (''b, a'')<sub>K</sub>. | |||
''If''. If (''a, b'')<sub>reverse</sub> = (''c, d'')<sub>reverse</sub>, | |||
(''b, a'')<sub>K</sub> = (''d, c'')<sub>K</sub>. Therefore ''b = d'' and ''a = c''. | |||
''Only if''. If ''a = c'' and ''b = d'', then {{''b''}, {''a, b''}} = {{''d''}, {''c, d''}}. | |||
Thus (''a, b'')<sub>reverse</sub> = (''c, d'')<sub>reverse</sub>. | |||
'''Short:'''<ref>For a formal [[Metamath]] proof of the adequacy of '''short''', see [http://us.metamath.org/mpegif/opthreg.html here (opthreg).] Also see Tourlakis (2003), Proposition III.10.1.</ref> | |||
''If'': Obvious. | |||
''Only if'': Suppose {''a'', {''a, b''}} = {''c'', {''c, d''}}. | |||
Then ''a'' is in the left hand side, and thus in the right hand side. | |||
Because equal sets have equal elements, one of ''a = c'' or ''a'' = {''c, d''} must be the case. | |||
:If ''a'' = {''c, d''}, then by similar reasoning as above, {''a, b''} is in the right hand side, so {''a, b''} = ''c'' or {''a, b''} = {''c, d''}. | |||
::If {''a, b''} = ''c'' then ''c'' is in {''c, d''} = ''a'' and ''a'' is in ''c'', and this combination contradicts the axiom of regularity, as {''a, c''} has no minimal element under the relation "element of." | |||
::If {''a, b''} = {''c, d''}, then ''a'' is an element of ''a'', from ''a'' = {''c, d''} = {''a, b''}, again contradicting regularity. | |||
:Hence ''a = c'' must hold. | |||
Again, we see that {''a, b''} = ''c'' or {''a, b''} = {''c, d''}. | |||
:The option {''a, b''} = ''c'' and ''a = c'' implies that ''c'' is an element of ''c'', contradicting regularity. | |||
:So we have ''a = c'' and {''a, b''} = {''c, d''}, and so: {''b''} = {''a, b''} \ {''a''} = {''c, d''} \ {''c''} = {''d''}, so ''b'' = ''d''. | |||
=== Quine-Rosser definition === | |||
[[J. Barkley Rosser|Rosser]] (1953)<ref>[[J. Barkley Rosser]], 1953. ''Logic for Mathematicians''. McGraw-Hill.</ref> employed a definition of the ordered pair due to [[Willard van Orman Quine|Quine]] which requires a prior definition of the [[natural number]]s. Let <math>\N</math> be the set of natural numbers | |||
and <math>x \setminus \N</math> be the elements of <math>x</math> not in <math>\N</math>. Define | |||
:<math>\varphi(x) = (x \setminus \N) \cup \{n+1 : n \in (x \cap \N) \}.</math> | |||
Applying this function simply increments every natural number in ''x''. In particular, <math>\varphi(x)</math> does not contain the number 0, so that for any sets ''x'' and ''y'', | |||
:<math>\varphi(x) \not= \{0\} \cup \varphi(y).</math> | |||
Define the ordered pair (''A'', ''B'') as | |||
:<math>(A, B) = \{\varphi(a) : a \in A\} \cup \{\varphi(b) \cup \{0\} : b \in B \}.</math> | |||
Extracting all the elements of the pair that do not contain 0 and undoing <math>\varphi</math> yields ''A''. Likewise, ''B'' can be recovered from the elements of the pair that do contain 0. | |||
In [[type theory]] and in outgrowths thereof such as the axiomatic set theory [[New Foundations|NF]], the Quine-Rosser pair has the same type as its projections and hence is termed a "type-level" ordered pair. Hence this definition has the advantage of enabling a [[function (mathematics)|function]], defined as a set of ordered pairs, to have a type only 1 higher than the type of its arguments. This definition works only if the set of natural numbers is infinite. This is the case in [[New Foundations|NF]], but not in [[type theory]] or in [[New Foundations|NFU]]. [[J. Barkley Rosser]] showed that the existence of such a type-level ordered pair (or even a "type-raising by 1" ordered pair) implies the [[axiom of infinity]]. For an extensive discussion of the ordered pair in the context of Quinian set theories, see Holmes (1998).<ref>Holmes, Randall (1998) ''[http://math.boisestate.edu/~holmes/holmes/head.pdf Elementary Set Theory with a Universal Set]''. Academia-Bruylant. The publisher has graciously consented to permit diffusion of this monograph via the web. Copyright is reserved.</ref> | |||
=== Morse definition === | |||
[[Morse-Kelley set theory]] (Morse 1965)<ref>Morse, Anthony P., 1965. ''A Theory of Sets''. Academic Press</ref> makes free use of [[proper class]]es. Morse defined the ordered pair so that its projections could be proper classes as well as sets. (The Kuratowski definition does not allow this.) He first defined ordered pairs whose projections are sets in Kuratowski's manner. He then ''redefined'' the pair | |||
:<math> (x, y) = (\{0\} \times s(x)) \cup (\{1\} \times s(y))</math> | |||
where the component Cartesian products are Kuratowski pairs of sets and where | |||
:<math> s(x) = \{\emptyset \} \cup \{\{t\} | t \in x\} </math> | |||
This renders possible pairs whose projections are proper classes. The Quine-Rosser definition above also admits [[proper class]]es as projections. Similarly the triple is defined as a 3-tuple as follows: | |||
:<math> (x, y, z) = (\{0\} \times s(x)) \cup (\{1\} \times s(y)) \cup (\{2\} \times s(z))</math> | |||
The use of the singleton set <math> s(x) </math> which has an inserted empty set allows tuples to have the uniqueness | |||
property that if a is an n-tuple and b is an m-tuple | |||
and a = b then n = m. Ordered triples which are defined as ordered pairs do not have this property with respect to ordered pairs. | |||
==Category theory== | |||
A category-theoretic [[Product (category theory)|product]] ''A'' × ''B'' in a [[category of sets]] represents the set of ordered pairs, with the first element coming from ''A'' and the second coming from ''B''. In this context the characteristic property above is a consequence of the [[universal property]] of the product and the fact that elements of a set ''X'' can be identified with morphisms from 1 (a one element set) to ''X''. While different objects may have the universal property, they are all [[naturally isomorphic]]. | |||
== References == | |||
<references /> | |||
{{Logic}} | |||
{{DEFAULTSORT:Ordered Pair}} | |||
[[Category:Basic concepts in set theory]] | |||
[[Category:Order theory]] | |||
[[Category:Type theory]] |
Revision as of 05:34, 12 January 2014
Template:Bots In mathematics, an ordered pair (a, b) is a pair of mathematical objects. The order in which the objects appear in the pair is significant: the ordered pair (a, b) is different from the ordered pair (b, a) unless a = b. (In contrast, the unordered pair {a, b} equals the unordered pair {b, a}.)
Ordered pairs are also called 2-tuples, or sequences of length 2; ordered pairs of scalars are also called 2-dimensional vectors. The entries of an ordered pair can be other ordered pairs, enabling the recursive definition of ordered n-tuples (ordered lists of n objects). For example, the ordered triple (a,b,c) can be defined as (a, (b,c)), i.e., as one pair nested in another.
In the ordered pair (a, b), the object a is called the first entry, and the object b the second entry of the pair. Alternatively, the objects are called the first and second coordinates, or the left and right projections of the ordered pair.
Cartesian products and binary relations (and hence functions) are defined in terms of ordered pairs.
Generalities
Let and be ordered pairs. Then the characteristic (or defining) property of the ordered pair is:
The set of all ordered pairs whose first entry is in some set A and whose second entry is in some set B is called the Cartesian product of A and B, and written A × B. A binary relation between sets A and B is a subset of A × B.
If one wishes to employ the notation for a different purpose (such as denoting open intervals on the real number line) the ordered pair may be denoted by the variant notation
The left and right projection of a pair p is usually denoted by π1(p) and π2(p), or by πl(p) and πr(p), respectively. In contexts where arbitrary n-tuples are considered, πni(t) is a common notation for the i-th component of an n tuple t.
Defining the ordered pair using set theory
The above characteristic property of ordered pairs is all that is required to understand the role of ordered pairs in mathematics. Hence the ordered pair can be taken as a primitive notion, whose associated axiom is the characteristic property. This was the approach taken by the N. Bourbaki group in its Theory of Sets, published in 1954, long after Kuratowski discovered his reduction (below). The Kuratowski definition was added in the second edition of Theory of Sets, published in 1970.
If one agrees that set theory is an appealing foundation of mathematics, then all mathematical objects must be defined as sets of some sort. Hence if the ordered pair is not taken as primitive, it must be defined as a set.[1] Several set-theoretic definitions of the ordered pair are given below.
Wiener's definition
Norbert Wiener proposed the first set theoretical definition of the ordered pair in 1914:[2]
He observed that this definition made it possible to define the types of Principia Mathematica as sets. Principia Mathematica had taken types, and hence relations of all arities, as primitive.
Wiener used {{b}} instead of {b} to make the definition compatible with type theory where all elements in a class must be of the same "type". With nesting b within an additional set its type is made equal to 's.
Hausdorff's definition
About the same time as Wiener (1914), Felix Hausdorff proposed his definition:
"where 1 and 2 are two distinct objects different from a and b."[3]
Kuratowski definition
In 1921 Kazimierz Kuratowski offered the now-accepted definition[4][5] of the ordered pair (a, b):
Note that this definition is used even when the first and the second coordinates are identical:
Given some ordered pair p, the property "x is the first coordinate of p" can be formulated as:
The property "x is the second coordinate of p" can be formulated as:
In the case that the left and right coordinates are identical, the right conjunct is trivially true, since Y1 ≠ Y2 is never the case.
This is how we can extract the first coordinate of a pair (using the notation for arbitrary intersection and arbitrary union):
This is how the second coordinate can be extracted:
Variants
The above Kuratowski definition of the ordered pair is "adequate" in that it satisfies the characteristic property that an ordered pair must satisfy, namely that . In particular, it adequately expresses 'order', in that is not necessarily true. There are other definitions, of similar or lesser complexity, that are equally adequate:
The reverse definition is merely a trivial variant of the Kuratowski definition, and as such is of no independent interest. The definition short is so-called because it requires two rather than three pairs of braces. Proving that short satisfies the characteristic property requires the Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory axiom of regularity.[6] Moreover, if one accepts the standard set-theoretic construction of the natural numbers, then 2 is defined as the set {0, 1} = {0, {0}}, which is indistinguishable from the pair (0, 0)short. Yet another disadvantage of the short pair is the fact, that even if a and b are of the same type, the elements of the short pair are not. (However, if a = b then the short version keeps having cardinality 2, which is something one might expect of any "pair", including any "ordered pair". Also note that the short version is used in Tarski–Grothendieck set theory, upon which the Mizar system is founded.)
Proving that definitions satisfy the characteristic property
Prove: (a, b) = (c, d) if and only if a = c and b = d.
Kuratowski:
If. If a = c and b = d, then {{a}, {a, b}} = {{c}, {c, d}}. Thus (a, b)K = (c, d)K.
Only if. Two cases: a = b, and a ≠ b.
If a = b:
- (a, b)K = {{a}, {a, b}} = {{a}, {a, a}} = {{a}}.
- (c, d)K = {{c}, {c, d}} = {{a}}.
- Thus {c} = {c, d} = {a}, which implies a = c and a = d. By hypothesis, a = b. Hence b = d.
If a ≠ b, then (a, b)K = (c, d)K implies {{a}, {a, b}} = {{c}, {c, d}}.
- Suppose {c, d} = {a}. Then c = d = a, and so {{c}, {c, d}} = {{a}, {a, a}} = {{a}, {a}} = {{a}}. But then {{a}, {a, b}} would also equal {{a}}, so that b = a which contradicts a ≠ b.
- Suppose {c} = {a, b}. Then a = b = c, which also contradicts a ≠ b.
- Therefore {c} = {a}, so that c = a and {c, d} = {a, b}.
- If d = a were true, then {c, d} = {a, a} = {a} ≠ {a, b}, a contradiction. Thus d = b is the case, so that a = c and b = d.
Reverse:
(a, b)reverse = {{b}, {a, b}} = {{b}, {b, a}} = (b, a)K.
If. If (a, b)reverse = (c, d)reverse, (b, a)K = (d, c)K. Therefore b = d and a = c.
Only if. If a = c and b = d, then {{b}, {a, b}} = {{d}, {c, d}}. Thus (a, b)reverse = (c, d)reverse.
Short:[7]
If: Obvious.
Only if: Suppose {a, {a, b}} = {c, {c, d}}. Then a is in the left hand side, and thus in the right hand side. Because equal sets have equal elements, one of a = c or a = {c, d} must be the case.
- If a = {c, d}, then by similar reasoning as above, {a, b} is in the right hand side, so {a, b} = c or {a, b} = {c, d}.
- If {a, b} = c then c is in {c, d} = a and a is in c, and this combination contradicts the axiom of regularity, as {a, c} has no minimal element under the relation "element of."
- If {a, b} = {c, d}, then a is an element of a, from a = {c, d} = {a, b}, again contradicting regularity.
- Hence a = c must hold.
Again, we see that {a, b} = c or {a, b} = {c, d}.
- The option {a, b} = c and a = c implies that c is an element of c, contradicting regularity.
- So we have a = c and {a, b} = {c, d}, and so: {b} = {a, b} \ {a} = {c, d} \ {c} = {d}, so b = d.
Quine-Rosser definition
Rosser (1953)[8] employed a definition of the ordered pair due to Quine which requires a prior definition of the natural numbers. Let be the set of natural numbers and be the elements of not in . Define
Applying this function simply increments every natural number in x. In particular, does not contain the number 0, so that for any sets x and y,
Define the ordered pair (A, B) as
Extracting all the elements of the pair that do not contain 0 and undoing yields A. Likewise, B can be recovered from the elements of the pair that do contain 0.
In type theory and in outgrowths thereof such as the axiomatic set theory NF, the Quine-Rosser pair has the same type as its projections and hence is termed a "type-level" ordered pair. Hence this definition has the advantage of enabling a function, defined as a set of ordered pairs, to have a type only 1 higher than the type of its arguments. This definition works only if the set of natural numbers is infinite. This is the case in NF, but not in type theory or in NFU. J. Barkley Rosser showed that the existence of such a type-level ordered pair (or even a "type-raising by 1" ordered pair) implies the axiom of infinity. For an extensive discussion of the ordered pair in the context of Quinian set theories, see Holmes (1998).[9]
Morse definition
Morse-Kelley set theory (Morse 1965)[10] makes free use of proper classes. Morse defined the ordered pair so that its projections could be proper classes as well as sets. (The Kuratowski definition does not allow this.) He first defined ordered pairs whose projections are sets in Kuratowski's manner. He then redefined the pair
where the component Cartesian products are Kuratowski pairs of sets and where
This renders possible pairs whose projections are proper classes. The Quine-Rosser definition above also admits proper classes as projections. Similarly the triple is defined as a 3-tuple as follows:
The use of the singleton set which has an inserted empty set allows tuples to have the uniqueness property that if a is an n-tuple and b is an m-tuple and a = b then n = m. Ordered triples which are defined as ordered pairs do not have this property with respect to ordered pairs.
Category theory
A category-theoretic product A × B in a category of sets represents the set of ordered pairs, with the first element coming from A and the second coming from B. In this context the characteristic property above is a consequence of the universal property of the product and the fact that elements of a set X can be identified with morphisms from 1 (a one element set) to X. While different objects may have the universal property, they are all naturally isomorphic.
References
- ↑ Quine has argued that the set-theoretical implementations of the concept of the ordered pair is a paradigm for the clarification of philosophical ideas (see "Word and Object", section 53). The general notion of such definitions or implementations are discussed in Thomas Forster "Reasoning about theoretical entities".
- ↑ Wiener's paper "A Simplification of the logic of relations" is reprinted, together with a valuable commentary on pages 224ff in van Heijenoort, Jean (1967), From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1979-1931, Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA, ISBN 0-674-32449-8 (pbk.). van Heijenoort states the simplification this way: "By giving a definition of the ordered pair of two elements in terms of class operations, the note reduced the theory of relations to that of classes".
- ↑ cf introduction to Wiener's paper in van Heijenoort 1967:224
- ↑ cf introduction to Wiener's paper in van Heijenoort 1967:224. van Heijenoort observes that the resulting set that represents the ordered pair "has a type higher by 2 than the elements (when they are of the same type)"; he offers references that show how, under certain circumstances, the type can be reduced to 1 or 0.
- ↑ One of the biggest reasons investing in a Singapore new launch is an effective things is as a result of it is doable to be lent massive quantities of money at very low interest rates that you should utilize to purchase it. Then, if property values continue to go up, then you'll get a really high return on funding (ROI). Simply make sure you purchase one of the higher properties, reminiscent of the ones at Fernvale the Riverbank or any Singapore landed property Get Earnings by means of Renting
In its statement, the singapore property listing - website link, government claimed that the majority citizens buying their first residence won't be hurt by the new measures. Some concessions can even be prolonged to chose teams of consumers, similar to married couples with a minimum of one Singaporean partner who are purchasing their second property so long as they intend to promote their first residential property. Lower the LTV limit on housing loans granted by monetary establishments regulated by MAS from 70% to 60% for property purchasers who are individuals with a number of outstanding housing loans on the time of the brand new housing purchase. Singapore Property Measures - 30 August 2010 The most popular seek for the number of bedrooms in Singapore is 4, followed by 2 and three. Lush Acres EC @ Sengkang
Discover out more about real estate funding in the area, together with info on international funding incentives and property possession. Many Singaporeans have been investing in property across the causeway in recent years, attracted by comparatively low prices. However, those who need to exit their investments quickly are likely to face significant challenges when trying to sell their property – and could finally be stuck with a property they can't sell. Career improvement programmes, in-house valuation, auctions and administrative help, venture advertising and marketing, skilled talks and traisning are continuously planned for the sales associates to help them obtain better outcomes for his or her shoppers while at Knight Frank Singapore. No change Present Rules
Extending the tax exemption would help. The exemption, which may be as a lot as $2 million per family, covers individuals who negotiate a principal reduction on their existing mortgage, sell their house short (i.e., for lower than the excellent loans), or take part in a foreclosure course of. An extension of theexemption would seem like a common-sense means to assist stabilize the housing market, but the political turmoil around the fiscal-cliff negotiations means widespread sense could not win out. Home Minority Chief Nancy Pelosi (D-Calif.) believes that the mortgage relief provision will be on the table during the grand-cut price talks, in response to communications director Nadeam Elshami. Buying or promoting of blue mild bulbs is unlawful.
A vendor's stamp duty has been launched on industrial property for the primary time, at rates ranging from 5 per cent to 15 per cent. The Authorities might be trying to reassure the market that they aren't in opposition to foreigners and PRs investing in Singapore's property market. They imposed these measures because of extenuating components available in the market." The sale of new dual-key EC models will even be restricted to multi-generational households only. The models have two separate entrances, permitting grandparents, for example, to dwell separately. The vendor's stamp obligation takes effect right this moment and applies to industrial property and plots which might be offered inside three years of the date of buy. JLL named Best Performing Property Brand for second year running
The data offered is for normal info purposes only and isn't supposed to be personalised investment or monetary advice. Motley Fool Singapore contributor Stanley Lim would not personal shares in any corporations talked about. Singapore private home costs increased by 1.eight% within the fourth quarter of 2012, up from 0.6% within the earlier quarter. Resale prices of government-built HDB residences which are usually bought by Singaporeans, elevated by 2.5%, quarter on quarter, the quickest acquire in five quarters. And industrial property, prices are actually double the levels of three years ago. No withholding tax in the event you sell your property. All your local information regarding vital HDB policies, condominium launches, land growth, commercial property and more
There are various methods to go about discovering the precise property. Some local newspapers (together with the Straits Instances ) have categorised property sections and many local property brokers have websites. Now there are some specifics to consider when buying a 'new launch' rental. Intended use of the unit Every sale begins with 10 p.c low cost for finish of season sale; changes to 20 % discount storewide; follows by additional reduction of fiftyand ends with last discount of 70 % or extra. Typically there is even a warehouse sale or transferring out sale with huge mark-down of costs for stock clearance. Deborah Regulation from Expat Realtor shares her property market update, plus prime rental residences and houses at the moment available to lease Esparina EC @ Sengkang - ↑ Tourlakis, George (2003) Lectures in Logic and Set Theory. Vol. 2: Set Theory. Cambridge Univ. Press. Proposition III.10.1.
- ↑ For a formal Metamath proof of the adequacy of short, see here (opthreg). Also see Tourlakis (2003), Proposition III.10.1.
- ↑ J. Barkley Rosser, 1953. Logic for Mathematicians. McGraw-Hill.
- ↑ Holmes, Randall (1998) Elementary Set Theory with a Universal Set. Academia-Bruylant. The publisher has graciously consented to permit diffusion of this monograph via the web. Copyright is reserved.
- ↑ Morse, Anthony P., 1965. A Theory of Sets. Academic Press