Carlos P. Garcia

From formulasearchengine
Revision as of 08:51, 28 January 2014 by en>ClueBot NG (Reverting possible vandalism by 112.203.133.78 to version by Spicyitalianmeatball. False positive? Report it. Thanks, ClueBot NG. (1672572) (Bot))
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)
Jump to navigation Jump to search

In modal logic, Sahlqvist formulas are a certain kind of modal formula with remarkable properties. The Sahlqvist correspondence theorem states that every Sahlqvist formula is canonical, and corresponds to a first-order definable class of Kripke frames.

Sahlqvist's definition characterizes a decidable set of modal formulas with first-order correspondents. Since it is undecidable, by Chagrova's theorem, whether an arbitrary modal formula has a first-order correspondent, there are formulas with first-order frame conditions that are not Sahlqvist [Chagrova 1991] (see the examples below). Hence Sahlqvist formulas define only a (decidable) subset of modal formulas with first-order correspondents.

Definition

Sahlqvist formulas are built up from implications, where the consequent is positive and the antecedent is of a restricted form.

  • A boxed atom is a propositional atom preceded by a number (possibly 0) of boxes, i.e. a formula of the form p (often abbreviated as ip for 0i<ω).
  • A Sahlqvist antecedent is a formula constructed using ∧, ∨, and from boxed atoms, and negative formulas (including the constants ⊥, ⊤).
  • A Sahlqvist implication is a formula AB, where A is a Sahlqvist antecedent, and B is a positive formula.
  • A Sahlqvist formula is constructed from Sahlqvist implications using ∧ and (unrestricted), and using ∨ on formulas with no common variables.

Examples of Sahlqvist formulas

pp
Its first-order corresponding formula is xRxx, and it defines all reflexive frames
pp
Its first-order corresponding formula is xy[RxyRyx], and it defines all symmetric frames
pp or pp
Its first-order corresponding formula is xyz[(RxyRyz)Rxz], and it defines all transitive frames
pp or pp
Its first-order corresponding formula is xy[Rxyz(RxzRzy)], and it defines all dense frames
pp
Its first-order corresponding formula is xyRxy, and it defines all right-unbounded frames (also called serial)
pp
Its first-order corresponding formula is xx1z0[Rxx1Rxz0z1(Rx1z1Rz0z1)], and it is the Church-Rosser property.

Examples of non-Sahlqvist formulas

pp
This is the McKinsey formula; it does not have a first-order frame condition.
(pp)p
The Löb axiom is not Sahlqvist; again, it does not have a first-order frame condition.
(pp)(qq)
The conjunction of the McKinsey formula and the (4) axiom has a first-order frame condition but is not equivalent to any Sahlqvist formula.

Kracht's theorem

When a Sahlqvist formula is used as an axiom in a normal modal logic, the logic is guaranteed to be complete with respect to the elementary class of frames the axiom defines. This result comes from the Sahlqvist completeness theorem [Modal Logic, Blackburn et al., Theorem 4.42]. But there is also a converse theorem, namely a theorem that states which first-order conditions are the correspondents of Sahlqvist formulas. Kracht's theorem states that any Sahlqvist formula locally corresponds to a Kracht formula; and conversely, every Kracht formula is a local first-order correspondent of some Sahlqvist formula which can be effectively obtained from the Kracht formula [Modal Logic, Blackburn et al., Theorem 3.59].

References

  • L. A. Chagrova, 1991. An undecidable problem in correspondence theory. Journal of Symbolic Logic 56:1261-1272.
  • Marcus Kracht, 1993. How completeness and correspondence theory got married. In de Rijke, editor, Diamonds and Defaults, pages 175-214. Kluwer.
  • Henrik Sahlqvist, 1975. Correspondence and completeness in the first- and second-order semantics for modal logic. In Proceedings of the Third Scandinavian Logic Symposium. North-Holland, Amsterdam.