Spectral theory of ordinary differential equations: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>Randomguess
 
en>Randomguess
Line 1: Line 1:
A '''donkey pronoun''' is a [[pronoun]] that is [[Bound variable pronoun|bound]] in [[semantics]] but not [[syntax]].<ref>
Emar Maier describes donkey pronouns as "bound but not [[c-command]]ed" in a [[Linguist List]] [http://www.linguistlist.org/issues/17/17-3393.html review] of Paul D. Elbourne's ''Situations and Individuals'' ([[MIT Press]], 2006).</ref><ref>Barker and Shan define a donkey pronoun as
"a pronoun that lies outside the restrictor of a [[Quantification|quantifier]] or the [[Antecedent (grammar)|antecedent]] of a [[Conditional clause|conditional]], yet [[covariance|covaries]] with some [[quantification]]al element inside it, usually an [[indefinite]]." Chris Barker and Chung-chieh Shan, [http://www.semanticsarchive.net/Archive/2Y2ODI4Z/barker-shan-donkeys.pdf 'Donkey Anaphora is Simply Binding'], colloquium presentation, Frankfurt, 2007.</ref>
Some writers prefer the term '''donkey anaphora''', since it is the [[Reference|referential]] aspects and [[discourse]] or [[syntax|syntactic]] context that are of interest to researchers (see [[anaphora (linguistics)|anaphora]]). The terms '''d-type''' or '''e-type pronoun''' are also used, [[mutual exclusivity|mutually exclusively]], dependent on theoretical approach to [[interpretation (logic)|interpretation]]. A sentence containing a donkey pronoun is sometimes called a ''[[donkey sentence]]''.


The term ''donkey pronoun'' was coined from a [[counterexample]] provided by [[Peter Geach]] (1962) to [[Richard Montague]]'s proposal for a generalized formal representation of [[quantification]] in [[natural language]]. The example was reused by [[David Kellogg Lewis|David Lewis]] (1975), [[Gareth Evans (philosopher)|Gareth Evans]] (1977) and many others, and is still quoted in recent publications. The original donkey sentence is as follows.
*Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it. — [[Peter Geach]], ''Reference and Generality''
This sentence is significant because it represents a class of well-formed natural language sentences that defy straightforward attempts to generate their [[formal language]] equivalents. The difficulty is with understanding how English speakers [[parsing|parse]] the scope of quantification in such sentences.<ref>
Lewis describes this as his motivation for considering the issue in the introduction to ''Papers in Philosophical Logic'', a collection of reprints of his articles. "There was no satisfactory way to assign relative scopes to quantifier phrases." ([[Cambridge University Press|CUP]], 1998: 2.)</ref>
Additionally, the [[indefinite article]] 'a' is normally understood as an [[existential quantifier]], but the most natural reading of the donkey sentence requires it to be understood as a nested [[universal quantifier]]. There are other features of the sentence that require careful consideration for adequate description.  (Notice, however, how reading "each" in place of "every" simplifies the formal analysis.)


Many sites require a payment for information that they claim will allow you to make a lot of money online. A good rule of thumb is to never pay anything to get that type of information. Legitimate sites may ask you to qualify by taking a test, but they will not require any type of payment. [http://www.comoganhardinheiro101.com/tag/negocio-mais-rentavel-da-internet/ ganhe dinheiro] People love handmade goods. They are very trendy right now, so if you are artsy, go make some money! So, if you are the creative type, whether it's sewing, knitting or any other craft work, now is the time to produce your goods. Both Etsy and eBay could be generating an income for you. <br><br><br>Make [http://Ganhedinheironainternet.comoganhardinheiro101.com extra money] on the side with email marketing. This is a great way to promote a company and use the subscribers that you have to your advantage. You will simply send a message or advertise a product to your large pool of subscribers and get paid money to do so. If you plan on making serious [http://www.comoganhardinheiro101.com/category/opcoes-binarias/ ganhar dinheiro pela internet] money online, make sure you've got the right equipment for the job. There's nothing more frustrating than trying to complete a job and your Internet times out, or is so slow that you miss a bid or other opportunity. Have the necessary equipment and make sure you're software is up to date too.<br><br>If you want to do something creative, consider ways to create viral videos. Brainstorm ideas that you think are rip riotously hilarious, then start putting them into action. Post them on YouTube, turn on ads and, if they work, watch the money start rolling in! Learn about marketing to see how you can get them even more popular. [http://www.comoganhardinheiro101.com/index.php como ganhar dinheiro na internet] If you know how to prepare taxes, you can earn money online. Apply for the necessary government licenses and then begin offering your services online. Many of today's top producers work from home with only their laptop and an email address. For best results, continually advertise your services throughout the year.<br><br>Don't buy every book about making money online. Most of the time, these books are sold by people whose claim to fame is that they are teaching people how to make money [http://www.comoganhardinheiro101.com/slide-central/ como conseguir dinheiro] online. Before you buy an e-book or book about making money, make sure that you know a little about the author, and that you have seen testimonials about the book.<br><br>When you work online, the world is your oyster. You are free to do, act and be as you wish, but only if you know what you're doing. If you want to turn your online work into a profitable career, use the tips you've read today and make it happen. When you are in a [http://www.comoganhardinheiro101.com/?p=71 como ganhar dinheiro] hurry to make money, reading about the topic may seem frustrating. The fact is that the more you know, the faster and better you will be at bringing in income. This article has given you the foundation you need, so build on it with experience and more learning.<br><br>Manage your [http://Comoganhardinheiro.comoganhardinheiro101.com/ time wisely] when you are trying to make money online. You may have a real-world job, which means you have to budget time wisely. Set a schedule that will allow you enough time to balance the two. Also make sure that you are being efficient in that time, so you don't run into stress [http://www.comoganhardinheiro101.com/?p=14 ganhando dinheiro na internet] about working online. Becoming a ghost writer is a great way to earn money online. There are people who need content for their websites, but who lack good writing skills. You can write for them and earn money for what you write. Many people are earning a good income writing for others this way.<br><br>Do you have a heart for customer service? If so, you can make money online answering phone calls for businesses. Additionally, you can make money by chatting online with a business's customer to help them solve problems and answer their questions. There are many customer service sites available including: LiveOps, Working Solutions [http://www.comoganhardinheiro101.com/category/opcoes-binarias/ ganhando dinheiro na internet] and ACD Direct. Write online to make money. There are quite a few legitimate companies that pay people to write articles online. You can find many different companies that will pay you to write different content with varying topics. If you enjoy writing, you should do research to look for companies that will pay you to write online.<br><br>Medical transcription can be a good way to make money online as a full time career. Formal training is required, and this can be costly. Additionally, it is necessary to have good computer and transcription equipment that works reliably. A great deal of work is available for people who are able and willing [http://www.comoganhardinheiro101.com/ como ganhar dinheiro pela internet] to invest in training and good equipment. Pay is quite substantial. You can sell your wares on the Internet to make money. Certain sites will help you to do your selling. You can personalize the t-shirts for your client. You can advertise by putting fliers up around the neighborhood or by using Craigslist.<br><br>If you have the ability to type quickly, you may consider transcription jobs. You need to have good headphones and the ability to keep up with what is being said. Often, the companies will have their own formatting guidelines. Familiarize yourself with these prior to beginning. Once you have, you can begin transcribing. [http://www.comoganhardinheiro101.com/homebox/ como ganhar dinheiro pela internet] What do you do? Do it for pay! A number of websites offer you points when you search through them and/or make purchases of items that you were planning to buy anyway. Take the points you earn and trade them for gift cards, gifts and sometimes even cash. Sites thatprovide this opportunity include Swagbucks and Mypoints.<br><br>As you can see from the above article, it is easy to understand how to make money online when you get the knowledge through great tips. You can join the millions of people worldwide who make money each day, if you [http://www.comoganhardinheiro101.com/ganhar-dinheiro-pela-internet-com-opcoes-binarias/ como ganhar dinheiro] pay close attention to the tips that you have just read. Making money online is a skill, and if you continue to study good tips and ideas such as these, there is no reason why you cannot make lots of money online.<br><br>
The donkey pronoun in the example sentence is the word ''it''.


that's a lie. Don't fall prey to these types of websites and always read the reviews before joining. Talking to experts in their field can help you to use [http://www.comoganhardinheiro101.com/como-ganhar-dinheiro-pela-internet/ como ganhar dinheiro pela internet] the Internet successfully. Try to network with people who do what you want to do. Doing these things can help give you an advantage over your competition.<br><br>If you're a performer, YouTube may help you earn income online. Here's more on [http://ganhandodinheironainternet.comoganhardinheiro101.com/ como ficar rico] take a look at http://ganhandodinheironainternet.comoganhardinheiro101.com/ Make a brief video clip showcasing your talents. Are you a whiz with cosmetics? Make online tutorials that focus on makeup. Do you view yourself as a comedian? Why not film a brief comedy routine on hot news topics? When your videos have [http://www.comoganhardinheiro101.com/?p=4 ganhe dinheiro na internet] been uploaded to the site, advertisements will be attached to your page and this will lead to payment. There are many ways you can make money online; all you need is some basic information. This article should have helped you get started. Use these tips to earn as much or as little as you need online.
There is nothing wrong with donkey sentences; they are grammatically correct, they are well-formed, their syntax is regular. They are also logically meaningful, they have well-defined [[truth conditions]], their semantics are unambiguous. It is precisely this that makes them interesting. The difficulty is with explaining how syntactic elements give rise to the semantic result and in a way that generalizes consistently with all other language use. Then, for example, we could program a computer to accurately translate natural language forms into [[logical form]].<ref>Alistair Knott, [http://www.cs.otago.ac.nz/staffpriv/alik/papers/cirevision.pdf 'An Algorithmic Framework for Specifying the Semantics of Discourse Relations',] ''Computational Intelligence'' '''16''' (2000).</ref> The question is, how are natural language users, apparently effortlessly, agreeing on the meaning of sentences like these?
 
There may be several equivalent ways of describing this process. In fact, [[Hans Kamp]] (1981) and [[Irene Heim]] (1982) independently proposed very similar accounts in different terminology, which they called [[discourse representation theory]] (DRT) and [[file change semantics]] (FCS) respectively.
 
In 2007, Adrian Brasoveanu published studies of donkey pronoun analogs in [[Hindi]], and analysis of complex and [[modal logic|modal]] versions of donkey pronouns in English.
 
==Discourse Representation Theory==
Donkey sentences became a major force in advancing [[semantics|semantic]] research in the 1980s, with the introduction of [[discourse representation theory]] (DRT). During that time, an effort was made to settle the inconsistencies which arose from the attempts to translate donkey sentences into [[first-order logic]].
 
Donkey sentences present the following problem, when represented in first-order logic: The systematic translation of every existential expression in the sentence into existential quantifiers produces an incorrect representation of the sentence, since it leaves a free occurrence of the variable y in BEAT(''x''.''y''):
 
: <math>  \forall x\, (\text{FARMER} (x) \and \exists y \,( \text{DONKEY}(y) \and \text{OWNS}(x,y)) \rightarrow \text{BEAT}(x,y)) </math>
 
Trying to extend the scope of the existential quantifier also does not solve the problem:
 
: <math>  \forall x \,\exists y\, (\text{FARMER} (x) \and \text{DONKEY}(y) \and \text{OWNS}(x,y) \rightarrow \text{BEAT}(x,y)) </math>
 
In this case, the logical translation fails to give correct truth conditions to donkey sentences:  Imagine a situation where there is a farmer owning a donkey and a pig, and not beating any of them. The formula will be true in that situation, because for each farmer we need to find at least one object that either is not a donkey owned by this farmer, or is beaten by the farmer. Hence, if this object denotes the pig, the sentence will be true in that situation.
 
A correct translation into first-order logic for the donkey sentence seems to be:
 
: <math>  \forall x\, \forall y\, (\text{FARMER} (x) \and \text{DONKEY}(y) \and \text{OWNS}(x,y) \rightarrow \text{BEAT}(x,y)) </math>
 
Unfortunately, this translation leads to a serious problem of inconsistency. Indefinites must sometimes be interpreted as existential quantifiers, and other times as universal quantifiers, without any apparent regularity.
 
The solution that [[Discourse representation theory|DRT]] provides for the donkey sentence problem can be roughly outlined as follows: The common semantic function of non-anaphoric [[noun phrase]]s is the introduction of a new [[discourse referent]], which is in turn available for the binding of anaphoric expressions. No quantifiers are introduced into the representation, thus overcoming the scope problem that the logical translations had.
 
==See also==
*[[Epsilon calculus]]
*[[Generic antecedent]]
*[[Lambda calculus]]
*[[Montague grammar]]
*[[Singular they]]
*[[Donkey sentence]]
 
==Notes==
{{Reflist}}
 
==Further reading==
{{Refbegin|colwidth=30em}}
*Abbott, Barbara. [http://www.springerlink.com/content/h341505636560743/ 'Donkey Demonstratives'.] ''[[Natural Language Semantics]]'' '''10''' (2002): 285–298.
*Barker, Chris. 'Individuation and Quantification'. ''[[Linguistic Inquiry]]'' '''30''' (1999): 683–691.
*Barker, Chris. 'Presuppositions for Proportional Quantifiers'. ''[[Natural Language Semantics]]'' '''4''' (1996): 237–259.
*Brasoveanu, Adrian. ''Structured Nominal and Modal Reference''. [[Rutgers University]] PhD [[dissertation]], 2007.
*Burgess, John P. '''E Pluribus Unum'': Plural Logic and Set Theory', ''Philosophia Mathematica'' '''12''' (2004): 193–221.
*Cheng, Lisa LS and C-T James Huang. [http://www.springerlink.com/content/gh791025x82x6766/ 'Two Types of Donkey Sentences'.] ''[[Natural Language Semantics]]'' '''4''' (1996): 121–163.
*Cohen, Ariel. ''Think Generic!'' Stanford, California: [[Center for the Study of Language and Information|CSLI Publications]], 1999.
*Conway, L. and S. Crain. 'Donkey Anaphora in Child Grammar'. In ''Proceedings of the North East Linguistics Society'' (NELS) '''25'''. [[University of Massachusetts Amherst]], 1995.
*[[Gareth Evans (philosopher)|Evans, Gareth]]. 'Pronouns'. ''[[Linguistic Inquiry]]'' '''11''' (1980): 337–362.
*[[Peter Geach|Geach Peter]]. ''Reference and Generality: An Examination of Some Medieval and Modern Theories''. Ithaca, New York: [[Cornell University Press]], 1962.
*Geurts, Bart. ''Presuppositions and Pronouns''. Oxford: [[Elsevier]], 1999.
*Harman, Gilbert. 'Anaphoric Pronouns as Bound Variables: Syntax or Semantics?' ''[[Language (journal)|Language]]'' '''52''' (1976): 78–81.
*[[Irene Heim|Heim, Irene]]. [http://www.springerlink.com/content/u533354617l67818/ 'E-Type Pronouns and Donkey Anaphora'.] ''[http://www.springer.com/linguistics/semantics/journal/10988 Linguistics and Philosophy]'' '''13''' (1990): 137–177.
*[[Irene Heim|Heim, Irene]]. ''The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases''. [[University of Massachusetts Amherst]] PhD [[dissertation]], 1982.
*Just, MA. 'Comprehending Quantified Sentences: The Relation between Sentencepicture and Semantic Memory Verification'. ''[[Cognitive Psychology]]'' '''6''' (1974): 216–236.
*Just, MA and PA Carpenter. 'Comprehension of Negation with Quantification'. ''Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior'' '''10''' (1971): 244–253.
*Kanazawa, Makoto. [http://www.springerlink.com/content/h1145h642pr81r5r/ 'Singular Donkey Pronouns Are Semantically Singular'.] ''[http://www.springer.com/linguistics/semantics/journal/10988 Linguistics and Philosophy]'' '''24''' (2001): 383–403.
*Kanazawa, Makoto. 'Weak vs. Strong Readings of Donkey Sentences and Monotonicity Inference in a Dynamic Setting'. ''[http://www.springer.com/linguistics/semantics/journal/10988 Linguistics and Philosophy]'' '''17''' (1994): 109–158.
*[[Manfred Krifka|Krifka, Manfred]]. 'Pragmatic Strengthening in Plural Predications and Donkey Sentences'. In ''Proceedings from Semantics and Linguistic Theory'' (SALT) '''6'''. Ithaca, New York: [[Cornell University]], 1996. Pages 136–153.
*Lappin, Shalom. 'An Intensional Parametric Semantics for Vague Quantifiers'. ''[http://www.springer.com/linguistics/semantics/journal/10988 Linguistics and Philosophy]'' '''23''' (2000): 599–620.
*Lappin, Shalom Lappin and Nissim Francez. 'E-type Pronouns, i-Sums, and Donkey Anaphora'. ''[http://www.springer.com/linguistics/semantics/journal/10988 Linguistics and Philosophy]'' '''17''' (1994): 391–428.
*Lappin, Shalom. 'Donkey Pronouns Unbound'. ''[[Theoretical Linguistics (journal)|Theoretical Linguistics]]'' '''15''' (1989): 263–286.
*[[David Kellogg Lewis|Lewis, David]]. ''Parts of Classes'', Oxford: [[Blackwell Publishing]], 1991.
*[[David Kellogg Lewis|Lewis, David]]. 'General Semantics'. ''Synthese'' '''22''' (1970): 18–27.
*[[Barbara Partee|Partee, Barbara H]]. 'Opacity, Coreference, and Pronouns'. ''Synthese'' '''21''' (1970): 359–385.
*[[Richard Montague|Montague, Richard]]. 'Universal Grammar'. ''Theoria'' '''26''' (1970): 373–398.
*[[Stephen Neale|Neale, Stephen]]. ''Descriptions''. Cambridge: [[MIT Press]], 1990.
*[[Stephen Neale|Neale, Stephen]]. 'Descriptive Pronouns and Donkey Anaphora'. ''[[Journal of Philosophy]]'' '''87''' (1990): 113-150.
*[[Willard Van Orman Quine|Quine, Willard Van Orman]]. ''[[Word and Object]]''. Cambridge, Massachusetts: [[MIT Press]], 1970.
*Rooij, Robert van. [http://jos.oxfordjournals.org/cgi/content/abstract/23/4/383 'Free Choice Counterfactual Donkeys'.] ''[[Journal of Semantics]]'' '''23''' (2006): 383–402.
*Yoon, Y-E. ''Weak and Strong Interpretations of Quantifiers and Definite NPs in English and Korean''. [[University of Texas at Austin]] PhD [[dissertation]], 1994.
* Kamp, Hans. and Reyle, U. 1993. From Discourse to Logic. Kluwer, Dordrecht.
* Kadmon, N. 2001. Formal Pragmatics: Semantics, Pragmatics, Presupposition, and Focus. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
{{Refend}}
 
==External links==
* [http://www.ims.uni-stuttgart.de/~hans/hpl-drt.pdf The Handbook of Philosophical Logic]
* [http://homepages.cwi.nl/~jve/papers/05/drt/drt.pdf Discourse Representation Theory]
* [http://www.alta.asn.au/events/altss_w2003_proc/public_lectures/knott/knott.html Introduction to Discourse Representation Theory]
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/discourse-representation-theory/ SEP Entry]
* [http://www.csi.uottawa.ca/~kbarker/teach/5386/donkey.html Archive of CSI 5386 Donkey Sentence Discussion]
*Barker, Chris. [http://books.google.com.au/books?id=ZIqGqn98OOMC&pg=PA303&lpg=PA303&dq=%22a+presuppositional+account+of+proportional+ambiguity%22&source=web&ots=0CAAK5sHZ8&sig=2DamB3jw3NRit9ebKBHXd7S2kwE&hl=en 'A Presuppositional Account of Proportional Ambiguity'.] In ''Proceedings of Semantic and Linguistic Theory'' (SALT) '''3'''. Ithaca, New York: [[Cornell University]], 1993. Pages 1–18.
*Brasoveanu, Adrian. [http://semanticsarchive.net/Archive/2FlYTZjO/donkey_pluralities_aug2007.html 'Donkey Pluralities: Plural Information States vs. Non-Atomic Individuals'.] In ''Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung'' '''11'''. Edited by E. Puig-Waldmüller. Barcelona: [[Pompeu Fabra University]], 2007. Pages 106–120.
*[[Gareth Evans (philosopher)|Evans, Gareth]]. 'Pronouns, Quantifiers, and Relative Clauses (I)'. ''Canadian Journal of Philosophy'' '''7''' (1977): 467–536.
*Geurts, Bart. [http://www.ru.nl/ncs/bart/papers/donkeys.pdf 'Donkey Business'.] ''[http://www.springer.com/linguistics/semantics/journal/10988 Linguistics and Philosophy]'' '''25''' (2002): 129–156.
*Huang, C-T James. [http://books.google.com.au/books?id=EHuiqtSwgv8C&pg=PR6&lpg=PR6&dq=logical+form+james+huang+university&source=web&ots=ApZYb_mjwz&sig=Y_HCVE4B51WqrsZkpPjXDKFTcOY&hl=en 'Logical Form'.] Chapter 3 in ''Government and Binding Theory and the Minimalist Program: Principles and Parameters in Syntactic Theory'' edited by Gert Webelhuth. Oxford and Cambridge: [[Blackwell Publishing]], 1995. Pages 127–177.
*[[Hans Kamp|Kamp, Hans]]. [http://books.google.com.au/books?hl=en&lr=&id=clYhtZ3RdTIC&oi=fnd&pg=PA1&dq=hans+kamp&ots=VpW0df39DM&sig=t_IQKL__NvUhJay3INoH7Bjdjlc 'A Theory of Truth and Semantic Representation'.] In J. Groenendijk and others (eds.). ''Formal Methods in the Study of Language''. Amsterdam: Mathematics Center, 1981.
*Kitagawa, Yoshihishi. [http://books.google.com.au/books?id=GA1Mr2xx5rUC&pg=PA54&lpg=PA54&dq=%22donkey+pronoun%22&source=web&ots=C19MpQ4-44&sig=o5tUkGAsG1pfOK6aRTZVKs28Z5s&hl=en 'Copying Variables'.] Chapter 2 in ''Functional Structure(s), Form and Interpretation: Perspectives from East Asian Languages''. Edited by Yen-hui Audrey Li and others. [[Routledge]], 2003. Pages 28–64.
*[[David Kellogg Lewis|Lewis, David]]. [http://books.google.com.au/books?id=Iqx80pAilKcC&pg=PA97&dq=%22adverbs+of+quantification%22+%22cast+of+characters%22&sig=XUVYIRzLEjd-nPAi_2wq-J1DcdA 'Adverbs of Quantification'.] In ''Formal Semantics of Natural Language''. Edited by Edward L Keenan. Cambridge: [[Cambridge University Press]], 1975. Pages 3–15.
*[[Richard Montague|Montague, Richard]]. [http://semantics.uchicago.edu/kennedy/classes/s08/semantics2/montague73.pdf 'The Proper Treatment of Quantification in Ordinary English'.] In KJJ Hintikka and others (eds). ''Proceedings of the 1970 Stanford Workshop on Grammar and Semantics''. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1973. Pages 212–242.
 
{{lexical categories|state=collapsed}}
[[Category:Pronouns]]
[[Category:Quantification]]

Revision as of 11:18, 26 October 2013

A donkey pronoun is a pronoun that is bound in semantics but not syntax.[1][2] Some writers prefer the term donkey anaphora, since it is the referential aspects and discourse or syntactic context that are of interest to researchers (see anaphora). The terms d-type or e-type pronoun are also used, mutually exclusively, dependent on theoretical approach to interpretation. A sentence containing a donkey pronoun is sometimes called a donkey sentence.

The term donkey pronoun was coined from a counterexample provided by Peter Geach (1962) to Richard Montague's proposal for a generalized formal representation of quantification in natural language. The example was reused by David Lewis (1975), Gareth Evans (1977) and many others, and is still quoted in recent publications. The original donkey sentence is as follows.

  • Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it. — Peter Geach, Reference and Generality

This sentence is significant because it represents a class of well-formed natural language sentences that defy straightforward attempts to generate their formal language equivalents. The difficulty is with understanding how English speakers parse the scope of quantification in such sentences.[3] Additionally, the indefinite article 'a' is normally understood as an existential quantifier, but the most natural reading of the donkey sentence requires it to be understood as a nested universal quantifier. There are other features of the sentence that require careful consideration for adequate description. (Notice, however, how reading "each" in place of "every" simplifies the formal analysis.)

The donkey pronoun in the example sentence is the word it.

There is nothing wrong with donkey sentences; they are grammatically correct, they are well-formed, their syntax is regular. They are also logically meaningful, they have well-defined truth conditions, their semantics are unambiguous. It is precisely this that makes them interesting. The difficulty is with explaining how syntactic elements give rise to the semantic result and in a way that generalizes consistently with all other language use. Then, for example, we could program a computer to accurately translate natural language forms into logical form.[4] The question is, how are natural language users, apparently effortlessly, agreeing on the meaning of sentences like these?

There may be several equivalent ways of describing this process. In fact, Hans Kamp (1981) and Irene Heim (1982) independently proposed very similar accounts in different terminology, which they called discourse representation theory (DRT) and file change semantics (FCS) respectively.

In 2007, Adrian Brasoveanu published studies of donkey pronoun analogs in Hindi, and analysis of complex and modal versions of donkey pronouns in English.

Discourse Representation Theory

Donkey sentences became a major force in advancing semantic research in the 1980s, with the introduction of discourse representation theory (DRT). During that time, an effort was made to settle the inconsistencies which arose from the attempts to translate donkey sentences into first-order logic.

Donkey sentences present the following problem, when represented in first-order logic: The systematic translation of every existential expression in the sentence into existential quantifiers produces an incorrect representation of the sentence, since it leaves a free occurrence of the variable y in BEAT(x.y):

Trying to extend the scope of the existential quantifier also does not solve the problem:

In this case, the logical translation fails to give correct truth conditions to donkey sentences: Imagine a situation where there is a farmer owning a donkey and a pig, and not beating any of them. The formula will be true in that situation, because for each farmer we need to find at least one object that either is not a donkey owned by this farmer, or is beaten by the farmer. Hence, if this object denotes the pig, the sentence will be true in that situation.

A correct translation into first-order logic for the donkey sentence seems to be:

Unfortunately, this translation leads to a serious problem of inconsistency. Indefinites must sometimes be interpreted as existential quantifiers, and other times as universal quantifiers, without any apparent regularity.

The solution that DRT provides for the donkey sentence problem can be roughly outlined as follows: The common semantic function of non-anaphoric noun phrases is the introduction of a new discourse referent, which is in turn available for the binding of anaphoric expressions. No quantifiers are introduced into the representation, thus overcoming the scope problem that the logical translations had.

See also

Notes

43 year old Petroleum Engineer Harry from Deep River, usually spends time with hobbies and interests like renting movies, property developers in singapore new condominium and vehicle racing. Constantly enjoys going to destinations like Camino Real de Tierra Adentro.

Further reading

Template:Refbegin

Template:Refend

External links

Template:Lexical categories

  1. Emar Maier describes donkey pronouns as "bound but not c-commanded" in a Linguist List review of Paul D. Elbourne's Situations and Individuals (MIT Press, 2006).
  2. Barker and Shan define a donkey pronoun as "a pronoun that lies outside the restrictor of a quantifier or the antecedent of a conditional, yet covaries with some quantificational element inside it, usually an indefinite." Chris Barker and Chung-chieh Shan, 'Donkey Anaphora is Simply Binding', colloquium presentation, Frankfurt, 2007.
  3. Lewis describes this as his motivation for considering the issue in the introduction to Papers in Philosophical Logic, a collection of reprints of his articles. "There was no satisfactory way to assign relative scopes to quantifier phrases." (CUP, 1998: 2.)
  4. Alistair Knott, 'An Algorithmic Framework for Specifying the Semantics of Discourse Relations', Computational Intelligence 16 (2000).